1
|
Lie RK, Chan FK, Grady C, Ng VH, Wendler D. Comparative effectiveness research: what to do when experts disagree about risks. BMC Med Ethics 2017; 18:42. [PMID: 28629343 PMCID: PMC5477349 DOI: 10.1186/s12910-017-0202-0] [Citation(s) in RCA: 3] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.4] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Download PDF] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 12/11/2016] [Accepted: 06/08/2017] [Indexed: 11/10/2022] Open
Abstract
BACKGROUND Ethical issues related to comparative effectiveness research, or research that compares existing standards of care, have recently received considerable attention. In this paper we focus on how Ethics Review Committees (ERCs) should evaluate the risks of comparative effectiveness research. MAIN TEXT We discuss what has been a prominent focus in the debate about comparative effectiveness research, namely that it is justified when "nothing is known" about the comparative effectiveness of the available alternatives. We argue that this focus may be misleading. Rather, we should focus on the fact that some experts believe that the evidence points in favor of one intervention, whereas other experts believe that the evidence favors the alternative(s). We will then introduce a case that illustrates this point, and based on that, discuss how ERCs should deal with such cases of expert disagreement. CONCLUSION We argue that ERCs have a duty to assess the range of expert opinions and based on that assessment arrive at a risk judgment about the study under consideration. We also argue that assessment of expert disagreement is important for the assignment of risk level to a clinical trial: what is the basis for expert opinions, how strong is the evidence appealed to by various experts, and how can clinical trial monitoring affect the possible increased risk of clinical trial participation.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Reidar K. Lie
- Department of Philosophy, University of Bergen, Sydnesplassen 12, 5020 Bergen, Norway
| | - Francis K.L. Chan
- Faculty of Medicine, The Chinese University of Hong Kong, Hong Kong Special Administration Region, People’s Republic of China
| | - Christine Grady
- Department of Bioethics, National Institutes of Health, 10 Center Drive, Bethesda, MD 20892 USA
| | - Vincent H. Ng
- Department of Mathematics and Science, Northern Virginia Community College, Woodbridge, VA 22191 USA
| | - David Wendler
- Department of Bioethics, National Institutes of Health, 10 Center Drive, Bethesda, MD 20892 USA
| |
Collapse
|
4
|
Welch MJ, Lally R, Miller JE, Pittman S, Brodsky L, Caplan AL, Uhlenbrauck G, Louzao DM, Fischer JH, Wilfond B. The ethics and regulatory landscape of including vulnerable populations in pragmatic clinical trials. Clin Trials 2015; 12:503-10. [PMID: 26374681 DOI: 10.1177/1740774515597701] [Citation(s) in RCA: 49] [Impact Index Per Article: 4.9] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 11/16/2022]
Abstract
Policies have been developed to protect vulnerable populations in clinical research, including the US federal research regulations (45 Code of Federal Regulations 46 Subparts B, C, and D). These policies generally recognize vulnerable populations to include pregnant women, fetuses, neonates, children, prisoners, persons with physical handicaps or mental disabilities, and disadvantaged persons. The aim has been to protect these populations from harm, often by creating regulatory and ethical checks that may limit their participation in many clinical trials. The recent increase in pragmatic clinical trials raises at least two questions about this approach. First, is exclusion itself a harm to vulnerable populations, as these groups may be denied access to understanding how health interventions work for them in clinical settings? Second, are groups considered vulnerable in traditional clinical trials also vulnerable in pragmatic clinical trials? We argue first that excluding vulnerable subjects from participation in pragmatic clinical trials can be harmful by preventing acquisition of data to meaningfully inform clinical decision-making in the future. Second, we argue that protections for vulnerable subjects in traditional clinical trial settings may not be translatable, feasible, or even ethical to apply in pragmatic clinical trials. We conclude by offering specific recommendations for appropriately protecting vulnerable research subjects in pragmatic clinical trials, focusing on pregnant women, fetuses, neonates, children, prisoners, persons with physical handicaps or mental disabilities, and disadvantaged persons.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Mary Jane Welch
- Human Subjects' Protection, College of Nursing, Rush University Medical Center, Chicago, IL, USA
| | - Rachel Lally
- Columbia University Medical Center, New York, NY, USA
| | - Jennifer E Miller
- Kenan Institute for Ethics, Duke University, Durham, NC, USA Edmond J. Safra Center for Ethics, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA, USA Division of Medical Ethics, NYU Langone Medical Center, New York, NY, USA
| | - Stephanie Pittman
- Human Subjects' Protection, Rush University Medical Center, Chicago, IL, USA
| | - Lynda Brodsky
- Cook County Health & Hospitals System, Chicago, IL, USA
| | - Arthur L Caplan
- Division of Medical Ethics, NYU Langone Medical Center, New York, NY, USA
| | - Gina Uhlenbrauck
- Duke Clinical Research Institute, Duke University, Durham, NC, USA
| | - Darcy M Louzao
- Duke Clinical Research Institute, Duke University, Durham, NC, USA
| | | | - Benjamin Wilfond
- Treuman Katz Center for Pediatric Bioethics, Seattle Children's Hospital, Seattle, WA, USA Division of Bioethics, Department of Pediatrics, University of Washington School of Medicine, Seattle, WA, USA
| |
Collapse
|