1
|
Espino O, Orenes I, Moreno-Ríos S. Illusory inferences in conditional expressions. Mem Cognit 2024; 52:1687-1699. [PMID: 38689204 DOI: 10.3758/s13421-024-01571-2] [Citation(s) in RCA: 0] [Impact Index Per Article: 0] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Accepted: 04/11/2024] [Indexed: 05/02/2024]
Abstract
A robber points a gun at a cashier and says: "Only one of these two options is true: If you conceal the combination to the safe, then I kill you; otherwise, if you don´t conceal the combination to the safe, then I kill you." Hearing this statement, most people conclude that, in either case, "I kill you." This is an illusory response, in fact; the valid conclusion states "I don´t kill you." The research reported here studied the roles that different expressions of conditionals ("if-then," "only if," and "if and only if") play in the illusory response. Three experiments show that participants inferred the conclusion "I kill you" from the conditional "if-then" and "I may or may not kill you" from the conditional "only if," while selecting both options with similar frequency for the biconditional "if and only if." These results shed light on the main theories of deductive reasoning.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Orlando Espino
- Department of Cognitive, Social, and Organizational Psychology, University of La Laguna, Tenerife, Spain.
| | - Isabel Orenes
- Department of Basic Psychology, National Distance Education University (UNED), Madrid, Spain
| | - Sergio Moreno-Ríos
- Department of Developmental and Educational Psychology & CIMCYC, University of Granada, Granada, Spain
| |
Collapse
|
2
|
Yuan Y, Duan Y, Li W, Ren J, Li Z, Yang C. Differences in the Default Mode Network of Temporal Lobe Epilepsy Patients Detected by Hilbert-Huang Transform Based Dynamic Functional Connectivity. Brain Topogr 2023:10.1007/s10548-023-00966-9. [PMID: 37115390 DOI: 10.1007/s10548-023-00966-9] [Citation(s) in RCA: 0] [Impact Index Per Article: 0] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Grants] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 04/25/2022] [Accepted: 04/15/2023] [Indexed: 04/29/2023]
Abstract
Resting-state functional connectivity, constructed via functional magnetic resonance imaging, has become an essential tool for exploring brain functions. Aside from the methods focusing on the static state, investigating dynamic functional connectivity can better uncover the fundamental properties of brain networks. Hilbert-Huang transform (HHT) is a novel time-frequency technique that can adapt to both non-linear and non-stationary signals, which may be an effective tool for investigating dynamic functional connectivity. To perform the present study, we investigated time-frequency dynamic functional connectivity among 11 brain regions of the default mode network by first projecting the coherence into the time and frequency domains, and subsequently by identifying clusters in the time-frequency domain using k-means clustering. Experiments on 14 temporal lobe epilepsy (TLE) patients and 21 age and sex-matched healthy controls were performed. The results show that functional connections in the brain regions of the hippocampal formation, parahippocampal gyrus, and retrosplenial cortex (Rsp) were reduced in the TLE group. However, the connections in the brain regions of the posterior inferior parietal lobule, ventral medial prefrontal cortex, and the core subsystem could hardly be detected in TLE patients. The findings not only demonstrate the feasibility of utilizing HHT in dynamic functional connectivity for epilepsy research, but also indicate that TLE may cause damage to memory functions, disorders of processing self-related tasks, and impairment of constructing a mental scene.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Ye Yuan
- Faculty of Environment and Life Sciences, Beijing University of Technology, Beijing, China
- Department of Bioengineering, Imperial College London, London, UK
| | - Ying Duan
- Beijing Universal Medical Imaging Diagnostic Center, Beijing, China
| | - Wan Li
- School of Computer Science and Engineering, Beijing Technology and Business University, Beijing, China
| | - Jiechuan Ren
- Beijing Tian Tan Hospital, Capital Medical University, Beijing, China
| | - Zhimei Li
- Beijing Tian Tan Hospital, Capital Medical University, Beijing, China
| | - Chunlan Yang
- Faculty of Environment and Life Sciences, Beijing University of Technology, Beijing, China.
| |
Collapse
|
3
|
Shao J, Tikiri Banda D, Baratgin J. A Study on the Sufficient Conditional and the Necessary Conditional With Chinese and French Participants. Front Psychol 2022; 13:787588. [PMID: 35282197 PMCID: PMC8907880 DOI: 10.3389/fpsyg.2022.787588] [Citation(s) in RCA: 0] [Impact Index Per Article: 0] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Download PDF] [Figures] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 09/30/2021] [Accepted: 01/10/2022] [Indexed: 11/18/2022] Open
Abstract
According to the weak version of linguistic relativity, also called the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis, the features of an individual’s native language influence his worldview and perception. We decided to test this hypothesis on the sufficient conditional and the necessary conditional, expressed differently in Chinese and French. In Chinese, connectors for both conditionals exist and are used in everyday life, while there is only a connector for the sufficient conditional in French. A first hypothesis follows from linguistic relativity: for the necessary conditional, better logic performance is expected in Chinese participants rather than French participants. As a second hypothesis, for all participants, we expect performance on the sufficient conditional to be better than on the necessary conditional. Indeed, despite the isomorphism of the two conditionals, they differ in how information is processed for reasoning. We decided to study reasoning under uncertainty as it reflects reality more accurately. To do so, we analyzed the coherence of participants using de Finetti’s theory for deduction under uncertainty. The results of our study show no significant difference in performance between Chinese and French participants, neither on the sufficient conditional nor on the necessary conditional. Thus, our first hypothesis derived from the weak version of linguistic relativity is not confirmed. In contrast, our results confirm the second hypothesis in two out of three inference schemas.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Jing Shao
- Laboratory Cognition Humaine et Artificielle, Université Paris 8, Paris, France.,Université de Haute-Alsace, Mulhouse, France
| | - Dilane Tikiri Banda
- Probability, Assessment, Reasoning and Inferences Studies (P-A-R-I-S) Association, Paris, France
| | - Jean Baratgin
- Laboratory Cognition Humaine et Artificielle, Université Paris 8, Paris, France.,Probability, Assessment, Reasoning and Inferences Studies (P-A-R-I-S) Association, Paris, France
| |
Collapse
|
4
|
Amore MD, Garofalo O, Martin-Sanchez V. Failing to Learn from Failure: How Optimism Impedes Entrepreneurial Innovation. ORGANIZATION SCIENCE 2021. [DOI: 10.1287/orsc.2020.1359] [Citation(s) in RCA: 9] [Impact Index Per Article: 3.0] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 11/20/2022]
Abstract
Extant research shows that entrepreneurs are typically overly optimistic about their ventures’ prospects and that such optimism hampers performance. We analyze how dispositional optimism affects the adjustments to entrepreneurs’ expectations after they receive negative feedback on their task performance. We then explore the relationship between optimism and the effectiveness of innovation. Exploiting unique firm-level data and a laboratory experiment involving 205 entrepreneurs, we find that dispositional optimism is negatively associated with both the likelihood and extent of belief updating in response to negative feedback. Furthermore, dispositional optimism triggers a discrepancy—between innovation inputs and outputs—that reduces a firm’s innovation effectiveness.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Mario Daniele Amore
- Department of Management and Technology, Bocconi University and CEPR, 20100 Milan, Italy
| | - Orsola Garofalo
- Department of Strategy and Innovation, Copenhagen Business School, 2000 Frederiksberg, Denmark
| | | |
Collapse
|
5
|
Content of relationship, number of alternatives and working memory capacity in conditional inferences. CURRENT PSYCHOLOGY 2021. [DOI: 10.1007/s12144-021-01966-3] [Citation(s) in RCA: 0] [Impact Index Per Article: 0] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 10/21/2022]
|
6
|
Abstract
Empirical evidence for the capacity to detect conflict between biased reasoning and normative principles has led to the proposal that reasoners have an intuitive grasp of some basic logical principles. In two studies, we investigate the boundary conditions of these logical intuitions by manipulating the logical complexity of problems where logical validity and conclusion believability conflict or not. Results pointed to evidence for successful conflict detection on the basic Modus Ponens (MP) inference, but also showed evidence for such a phenomenon on the more complex Modus Tollens (MT) inference. This suggests that both the MP and the MT inferences are simple enough for reasoners to have an intuitive grasp of their logical structure. The boundaries of logical intuition might thus reside in problems of greater complexity than these inferences. We also observed that on the invalid Affirmation of the Consequent (AC) and Denial of the Antecedent (DA) inferences, participants showed higher accuracy on the inference that was expected to be more complex (DA), and no evidence for successful conflict detection was found on these forms. Implications for the logical intuition framework are discussed.
Collapse
|
7
|
Abstract
This paper addresses the issue of how negative components affect people's ability to draw conditional inferences. The study was motivated by an attempt to resolve a difficulty for the mental models theory of Johnson-Laird and Byrne, whose account of matching bias in the selection task is apparently inconsistent with Johnson-Laird's explanation of the double negation effects in conditional inference reported by Evans, Clibbens, and Rood (1995). Two experiments are reported, which investigate frequencies of conditional inferences with task presentation similar to that of the selection task in two respects: the presence of a picture of four cards and the use of implicit negations in the premises. The latter variable was shown to be critical and demonstrated a new phenomenon: Conditional inferences of all kinds are substantially suppressed when based on implicitly negative premises. This phenomenon was shown to operate independently of and in addition to the double negation effect. A third experiment showed that the implicit negation effect could be extended to the paradigm in which people are asked to produce their own conclusions. It is argued that these two effects can be explained within either the mental models theory or the inference rule theory, of propositional reasoning, but that each will require some revision in order to offer a convincing account.
Collapse
|
8
|
Evans JS, Legrenzi P, Girotto V. The Influence of Linguistic Form on Reasoning: The Case of Matching Bias. ACTA ACUST UNITED AC 2018. [DOI: 10.1080/713755805] [Citation(s) in RCA: 14] [Impact Index Per Article: 2.3] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 10/17/2022]
Abstract
A well-established phenomenon in reasoning research is matching bias: a tendency to select information that matches the lexical content of propositional statements, regardless of the logically critical presence of negations. Previous research suggested, however, that the effect might be restricted to reasoning with conditional statements. This paper reports two experiments in which participants were required to construct or identify true and false cases of propositional rules of several kinds, including universal statements, disjunctions, and negated conjunctions. Matching bias was observed across all rule types but largely restricted to problems where participants were required to falsify rather than to verify the rules. A third experiment showed a similar generalization across linguistic forms in the Wason selection task with only if conditionals substituted for universals. The results are discussed with reference to contemporary theories of propositional reasoning.
Collapse
|
9
|
Oberauer K, Geiger SM, Fischer K, Weidenfeld A. Two meanings of “if”? Individual differences in the interpretation of conditionals. Q J Exp Psychol (Hove) 2018; 60:790-819. [PMID: 17514595 DOI: 10.1080/17470210600822449] [Citation(s) in RCA: 27] [Impact Index Per Article: 4.5] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 10/24/2022]
Abstract
This work investigates the nature of two distinct response patterns in a probabilistic truth table evaluation task, in which people estimate the probability of a conditional on the basis of frequencies of the truth table cases. The conditional-probability pattern reflects an interpretation of conditionals as expressing a conditional probability. The conjunctive pattern suggests that some people treat conditionals as conjunctions, in line with a prediction of the mental-model theory. Experiments 1 and 2 rule out two alternative explanations of the conjunctive pattern. It does not arise from people believing that at least one case matching the conjunction of antecedent and consequent must exist for a conditional to be true, and it does not arise from people adding the converse to the given conditional. Experiment 3 establishes that people's response patterns in the probabilistic truth table task are very consistent across different conditionals, and that the two response patterns generalize to conditionals with negated antecedents and consequents. Individual differences in rating the probability of a conditional were loosely correlated with corresponding response patterns in a classical truth table evaluation task, but there was little association with people's evaluation of deductive inferences from conditionals as premises. A theoretical framework is proposed that integrates elements from the conditional-probability view with the theory of mental models.
Collapse
|
10
|
Oberauer K, Hörnig R, Weidenfeld A, Wilhelm O. Effects of Directionality in Deductive Reasoning: II. Premise Integration and Conclusion Evaluation. ACTA ACUST UNITED AC 2018; 58:1225-47. [PMID: 16194956 DOI: 10.1080/02724980443000566] [Citation(s) in RCA: 11] [Impact Index Per Article: 1.8] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 10/25/2022]
Abstract
Previous research (Oberauer & Wilhelm, 2000) has shown an inherent directionality between the two terms linked in premises of typical deductive reasoning tasks. With three experiments we investigated the effect of inherent directionality on the time to integrate two premises and for the derivation of a conclusion. We varied figure (i.e., order of terms in the premises) and direction of inference (i.e., order of terms in the conclusion) in deduction tasks from various domains (propositional reasoning, syllogisms, spatial, temporal, and linear order reasoning). Effects of figure on premise reading times varied with the directionality of the relations. Effects of direction of inference reflected the same directionality for a subset of relations. We propose that two factors are jointly responsible for a large part of observed directionality effects in premise integration: the inherent directionality of relational statements and a general advantage for a given–new order of terms in the second premise. Difficulty of deriving a conclusion is affected by the directionality or relations if and only if the relation is semantically asymmetric, so that the directionality must be preserved in the integrated mental model.
Collapse
|
11
|
Espino O, Morales T, Bolaños-Medina A. Directional effect in double conditionals with a construction task: The semantic hypothesis. Acta Psychol (Amst) 2017; 179:96-103. [PMID: 28753484 DOI: 10.1016/j.actpsy.2017.07.007] [Citation(s) in RCA: 0] [Impact Index Per Article: 0] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 02/21/2016] [Revised: 06/27/2017] [Accepted: 07/12/2017] [Indexed: 10/19/2022] Open
Abstract
The goal of this paper is to test the main predictions of the semantic hypothesis about the directional effect in double conditionals (such as, 'A only if B/only if C, B') with a construction task. The semantic hypothesis claims that directional effect can be explained by the inherent directionality of the relation between the relatum and the target object of the premises. According to this hypothesis, a directional effect should occur if only one of the end-terms of the premises takes the role of relatum: a) if the end-term that plays the role of relatum is in the first premise, a forward directional effect is predicted (from A to C); and b) if the end-term that plays the role of relatum is in the second premise, a backward directional effect is predicted (from C to A). On the other hand, it claims that there should be no directional effect when both end-terms take the role of relatum or when neither of the end-terms plays the role of relatum. Three experiments confirmed the main predictions of the semantic hypothesis in a construction task.
Collapse
|
12
|
Ruiz-Ballesteros JA, Moreno-Ríos S. Concessive and semifactual interpretations during reasoning with multiple conditionals. Q J Exp Psychol (Hove) 2017; 70:1140-1150. [DOI: 10.1080/17470218.2016.1172098] [Citation(s) in RCA: 3] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.4] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 10/22/2022]
Abstract
The present research evaluates how people integrate factual ‘if then’ and semifactual ‘even if’ conditional premises in an inference task. The theory of mental models establishes that semifactual statements are represented by two mental models with different epistemic status: ‘A & B’ is conjectured and ‘not-A & B’ is presupposed. However, following the principle of cognitive economy in tasks with a high working memory load such as reasoning with multiple conditionals, people could simplify the deduction process in two ways, by discarding: (a) the presupposed case and/or (b) the epistemic status information. In Experiment 1 and Experiment 2, we evaluated each of these hypotheses. In Experiment 1, participants make inferences from two conditionals: two factual conditionals or one factual and one semifactual, with different representations. In Experiment 2, participants make inferences with a factual conditional followed by two different semifactual conditionals that share the same representations but differ in their epistemic status. Accuracy and latency data suggest that people think of both the conjectured and the presupposed situations, but do not codify the epistemic status of either when the task does not require it. The results are discussed through theoretical predictions about how people make inferences from different connected conditionals.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- José Antonio Ruiz-Ballesteros
- Facultad de Psicología, Centro de Investigación Mente, Cerebro Y Comportamiento, Campus Universitario de La Cartuja, Granada, Spain
| | - Sergio Moreno-Ríos
- Facultad de Psicología, Campus Universitario de La Cartuja, Granada, Spain
| |
Collapse
|
13
|
Probabilistic conditional reasoning: Disentangling form and content with the dual-source model. Cogn Psychol 2016; 88:61-87. [DOI: 10.1016/j.cogpsych.2016.06.005] [Citation(s) in RCA: 13] [Impact Index Per Article: 1.6] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 03/30/2015] [Revised: 03/18/2016] [Accepted: 06/21/2016] [Indexed: 11/18/2022]
|
14
|
Abstract
In most longitudinal studies, researchers take the stability of a latent dimension for granted.This article shows that items assumed to measure a given construct can change their meaning during developmental progress or across cohorts.The authors suggest that Rasch models offer a viable approach to assessing such aspects of dimensionality.First, they outline the general ideas of the Rasch model.Then, they discuss how mixed Rasch models, an exploratory approach for identifying latent classes of participants within which unidimensionality holds, can be used to assess the dimensionality of a given item set.To illustrate their ideas, the authors present data from a study on adolescents’ deductive reasoning that clearly show that the same test items can be measuring qualitatively different latent traits in different subsamples or at different time points.
Collapse
|
15
|
Espino O, Sánchez-Curbelo I, Bolaños-Medina A. Directionality Effect in Double Conditionals. THE SPANISH JOURNAL OF PSYCHOLOGY 2015; 18:E57. [PMID: 26239471 DOI: 10.1017/sjp.2015.42] [Citation(s) in RCA: 1] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.1] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 06/04/2023]
Abstract
Directionality effect in deductive reasoning is a very well-known phenomenon that shows that the percentage of forward or backward inferences that participants make depends on the conditional form used. A new extension of the semantic hypothesis (Oberauer & Wilhelm, 2000) is presented to explain the directionality effect in double conditionals with different directionality. This hypothesis claims that the directional effect depends on which term plays the role of relatum. It also makes several novel claims which have been confirmed in three experiments: Experiments 1 and 2 showed there were more forward than backward inferences when the end-term that played the role of relatum was in the first premise, experiment 1: t (45) = 2.73, p < .01, experiment 2: t (38) = 12.06, p < .05, but there were more backward than forward inferences when the end-term that played the role of relatum was in the second premise, experiment 1: t (45) = 2.84, p < .01, experiment 2: t (38) = 2.21, p < .04. Experiment 3 showed that there was no directional effect when both end-terms played the role of relatum, t (34) = 1.39, p = .17, or when both middle-terms (or neither of the end-terms) played the role of relatum, t (34) = .78, p = .44. These experiments confirmed the predictions of the new extension of the semantic hypothesis.
Collapse
|
16
|
Johnson ED, Tubau E. Comprehension and computation in Bayesian problem solving. Front Psychol 2015; 6:938. [PMID: 26283976 PMCID: PMC4515557 DOI: 10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00938] [Citation(s) in RCA: 28] [Impact Index Per Article: 3.1] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Download PDF] [Figures] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 03/30/2015] [Accepted: 06/22/2015] [Indexed: 11/25/2022] Open
Abstract
Humans have long been characterized as poor probabilistic reasoners when presented with explicit numerical information. Bayesian word problems provide a well-known example of this, where even highly educated and cognitively skilled individuals fail to adhere to mathematical norms. It is widely agreed that natural frequencies can facilitate Bayesian inferences relative to normalized formats (e.g., probabilities, percentages), both by clarifying logical set-subset relations and by simplifying numerical calculations. Nevertheless, between-study performance on "transparent" Bayesian problems varies widely, and generally remains rather unimpressive. We suggest there has been an over-focus on this representational facilitator (i.e., transparent problem structures) at the expense of the specific logical and numerical processing requirements and the corresponding individual abilities and skills necessary for providing Bayesian-like output given specific verbal and numerical input. We further suggest that understanding this task-individual pair could benefit from considerations from the literature on mathematical cognition, which emphasizes text comprehension and problem solving, along with contributions of online executive working memory, metacognitive regulation, and relevant stored knowledge and skills. We conclude by offering avenues for future research aimed at identifying the stages in problem solving at which correct vs. incorrect reasoners depart, and how individual differences might influence this time point.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Eric D. Johnson
- Department of Basic Psychology, University of BarcelonaBarcelona, Spain
- Research Institute for Brain, Cognition, and Behavior (IR3C)Barcelona, Spain
| | - Elisabet Tubau
- Department of Basic Psychology, University of BarcelonaBarcelona, Spain
- Research Institute for Brain, Cognition, and Behavior (IR3C)Barcelona, Spain
| |
Collapse
|
17
|
Singmann H, Klauer KC, Over D. New normative standards of conditional reasoning and the dual-source model. Front Psychol 2014; 5:316. [PMID: 24860516 PMCID: PMC4029011 DOI: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00316] [Citation(s) in RCA: 31] [Impact Index Per Article: 3.1] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Download PDF] [Figures] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 11/04/2013] [Accepted: 03/26/2014] [Indexed: 11/28/2022] Open
Abstract
There has been a major shift in research on human reasoning toward Bayesian and probabilistic approaches, which has been called a new paradigm. The new paradigm sees most everyday and scientific reasoning as taking place in a context of uncertainty, and inference is from uncertain beliefs and not from arbitrary assumptions. In this manuscript we present an empirical test of normative standards in the new paradigm using a novel probabilized conditional reasoning task. Our results indicated that for everyday conditional with at least a weak causal connection between antecedent and consequent only the conditional probability of the consequent given antecedent contributes unique variance to predicting the probability of conditional, but not the probability of the conjunction, nor the probability of the material conditional. Regarding normative accounts of reasoning, we found significant evidence that participants' responses were confidence preserving (i.e., p-valid in the sense of Adams, 1998) for MP inferences, but not for MT inferences. Additionally, only for MP inferences and to a lesser degree for DA inferences did the rate of responses inside the coherence intervals defined by mental probability logic (Pfeifer and Kleiter, 2005, 2010) exceed chance levels. In contrast to the normative accounts, the dual-source model (Klauer et al., 2010) is a descriptive model. It posits that participants integrate their background knowledge (i.e., the type of information primary to the normative approaches) and their subjective probability that a conclusion is seen as warranted based on its logical form. Model fits showed that the dual-source model, which employed participants' responses to a deductive task with abstract contents to estimate the form-based component, provided as good an account of the data as a model that solely used data from the probabilized conditional reasoning task.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Henrik Singmann
- Institut für Psychologie, Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg Freiburg, Germany
| | | | - David Over
- Department of Psychology, Durham University Durham, UK
| |
Collapse
|
18
|
Abstract
We report the results of two experiments investigating conditional inferences from conditionalunlessassertions, such asJuan is not in León unless Nuria is in Madrid. Experiments 1 and 2 check Fillenbaum's hypothesis about the semantic similarity ofunlesswithif notandonly ifassertions; both also examine inferential endorsements (Experiment 1) and endorsements and latencies (Experiment 2) of the four logically equivalent conditional formulations:if A then B, if not-B then not-A, A only if Bandnot-A unless B. The results of these experiments show the similarity ofunlessandonly if, confirming that the representation of both conditionals from the outset probably include two possibilities directionally oriented from B to A; results also confirm the especial difficulty ofunlessassertions. The implications of the results are discussed in the context of recent psychological and linguistic theories of the meaning ofunless.
Collapse
|
19
|
Valiña MD, Seoane G, Ferraces MJ, Martín M. La tarea de selección de Wason: ¿efecto de contenido, efecto de las instrucciones o ambos? STUDIES IN PSYCHOLOGY 2014. [DOI: 10.1174/02109399860341924] [Citation(s) in RCA: 3] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.3] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 11/21/2022] Open
|
20
|
Espino O, Byrne RMJ. The compatibility heuristic in non-categorical hypothetical reasoning: inferences between conditionals and disjunctions. Cogn Psychol 2013; 67:98-129. [PMID: 23968595 DOI: 10.1016/j.cogpsych.2013.05.002] [Citation(s) in RCA: 8] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.7] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 10/27/2012] [Revised: 05/28/2013] [Accepted: 05/29/2013] [Indexed: 11/30/2022]
Abstract
A new theory explains how people make hypothetical inferences from a premise consistent with several alternatives to a conclusion consistent with several alternatives. The key proposal is that people rely on a heuristic that identifies compatible possibilities. It is tested in 7 experiments that examine inferences between conditionals and disjunctions. Participants accepted inferences between conditionals and inclusive disjunctions when a compatible possibility was immediately available, in their binary judgments that a conclusion followed or not (Experiment 1a) and ternary judgments that included it was not possible to know (Experiment 1b). The compatibility effect was amplified when compatible possibilities were more readily available, e.g., for 'A only if B' conditionals (Experiment 2). It was eliminated when compatible possibilities were not available, e.g., for 'if and only if A B' bi-conditionals and exclusive disjunctions (Experiment 3). The compatibility heuristic occurs even for inferences based on implicit negation e.g., 'A or B, therefore if C D' (Experiment 4), and between universals 'All A's are B's' and disjunctions (Experiment 5a) and universals and conditionals (Experiment 5b). The implications of the results for alternative theories of the cognitive processes underlying hypothetical deductions are discussed.
Collapse
|
21
|
Castilho GMD, Janczura GA. Raciocínio condicional: a conclusão depende do conhecimento armazenado na memória. ESTUDOS DE PSICOLOGIA (NATAL) 2012. [DOI: 10.1590/s1413-294x2012000100007] [Citation(s) in RCA: 2] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.2] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 11/22/2022] Open
Abstract
Exemplos alternativos armazenados na memória são fundamentais para a correta interpretação da proposição condicional "Se P, então Q". Esse artigo propõe que a força associativa e o tamanho da categoria semântica têm um papel crítico na ativação de modelos alternativos envolvidos neste tipo de raciocínio. Adicionalmente, quanto mais modelos alternativos, justificados em função do tipo de inferência, maior a dificuldade da tarefa, dada a sobrecarga de informação na memória de trabalho. Dois Experimentos testaram essas hipóteses, sendo que os resultados do Experimento 1 confirmaram efeitos significativos da força associativa, tamanho da categoria, tipo de inferência e interação entre fatores. O Experimento 2 evidenciou que os efeitos de força associativa são contextos-dependentes devido à redução do campo semântico. Esses achados são consistentes com a hipótese de que o conhecimento armazenado na memória tem um papel importante no raciocínio condicional.
Collapse
|
22
|
Kempert S, Hardy I. Effekte von früher Zweisprachigkeit auf das deduktive Schließen im Grundschulalter. ZEITSCHRIFT FUR ENTWICKLUNGSPSYCHOLOGIE UND PADAGOGISCHE PSYCHOLOGIE 2012. [DOI: 10.1026/0049-8637/a000060] [Citation(s) in RCA: 3] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.3] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 11/04/2022]
Abstract
Zusammenfassung. Im vorliegenden Beitrag werden mehrsprachigkeitsbedingte Vorteile in den exekutiven Funktionen anhand von Konditionalaussagen der Form „Wenn P, dann Q” untersucht. Dabei interessieren v.a. Aufgaben mit kontraintuitiven und abstrakten Inhalten, da diese Arten von Syllogismen besondere Anforderungen an die Aufmerksamkeitskontrolle und Inhibitionsfähigkeit stellen. In einer Studie mit N = 54 monolingual deutschen und bilingual deutsch-englischen Schülerinnen und Schülern der dritten Klasse konnten die angenommenen Vorteile für Zweisprachige belegt werden. Zudem konnten in Abgrenzung dazu keine Unterschiede in den Lösungsraten bei Syllogismen mit konkreten Inhalten sowie mit erleichternden oder erschwerenden Zusatzinformationen beobachtet werden. Die Ergebnisse werden hinsichtlich der Entwicklung des deduktiven Schließens sowie der Relevanz für schulisches Lernen diskutiert.
Collapse
|
23
|
García-Madruga JA, Carriedo N, Moreno-Ríos S. The semantics of 'unless' conditionals: evidence from 'unless' and disjunctive inferences. SPANISH JOURNAL OF PSYCHOLOGY 2011; 14:569-79. [PMID: 22059303 DOI: 10.5209/rev_sjop.2011.v14.n2.5] [Citation(s) in RCA: 2] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.2] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Track Full Text] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 11/20/2022]
Abstract
We report the results of an experiment investigating conditional inferences from conditional assertions such as 'Juan won't go to León unless Nuria goes to Madrid' and 'Either Nuria goes to Madrid or Juan won't go to León'. This experiment addresses Dancygier's claims about the semantics of 'unless' by examining inferential endorsements of 'not-A unless B' and 'Either B or not-A' in the canonical order, presenting the categorical premise after the conditional assertions, and in the inverse order, presenting the categorical premise before the conditional assertions. The results of the experiment confirm that the representation of 'unless' includes two possibilities, although as Dancygier holds one of the possibilities may not be complete. The implications of the results are discussed in the context of the strategic nature of conditional reasoning and recent convergent theories of linguistic processing.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Juan A García-Madruga
- Departamento de Psicología Evolutiva y de la Educación, Universidad Nacional de Educación a Distancia, Madrid, Spain.
| | | | | |
Collapse
|
24
|
Schroyens W, Braem S. The initial representation in reasoning towards an interpretation of conditional sentences. Q J Exp Psychol (Hove) 2010; 64:339-62. [PMID: 21104563 DOI: 10.1080/17470218.2010.513734] [Citation(s) in RCA: 3] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.2] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 10/18/2022]
Abstract
All accounts of human reasoning (whether presented at the symbolic or subsymbolic level) have to reckon with the temporal organization of the human processing systems and the ephemeral nature of the representations it uses. We present three new empirical tests for the hypothesis that people commence the interpretational process by constructing a minimal initial representation. In the case of if A then C the initial representation captures the occurrence of the consequent, C, within the context of the antecedent, A. Conditional inference problems are created by a categorical premise that affirms or denies A or C. The initial representation allows an inference when the explicitly represented information matches (e.g., the categorical premise A affirms the antecedent "A") but not when it mismatches (e.g., "not-A" denies A). Experiments 1 and 2 confirmed that people tend to accept the conclusion that "nothing follows" for the denial problems, as indeed they do not have a determinate initial-model conclusion. Experiment 3 demonstrated the other way round that the effect of problem type (affirmation versus denial) is reduced when we impede the possibility of inferring a determinate conclusion on the basis of the initial representation of both the affirmation and the denial problems.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Walter Schroyens
- Laboratory of Experimental Psychology, University of Leuven, Leuven, Belgium.
| | | |
Collapse
|
25
|
Evans JS. Matching Bias in Conditional Reasoning: Do We Understand it After 25 Years? THINKING & REASONING 2010. [DOI: 10.1080/135467898394247] [Citation(s) in RCA: 67] [Impact Index Per Article: 4.8] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 10/16/2022]
|
26
|
|
27
|
Schroyens W. A meta-analytic review of thinking about what is true, possible, and irrelevant in reasoning from or reasoning about conditional propositions. ACTA ACUST UNITED AC 2010. [DOI: 10.1080/09541440902928915] [Citation(s) in RCA: 14] [Impact Index Per Article: 1.0] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 10/19/2022]
|
28
|
|
29
|
|
30
|
Egan SM, García-Madruga JA, Byrne RM. Indicative and counterfactual 'only if' conditionals. Acta Psychol (Amst) 2009; 132:240-9. [PMID: 19695557 DOI: 10.1016/j.actpsy.2009.07.005] [Citation(s) in RCA: 11] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.7] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 10/29/2008] [Revised: 05/29/2009] [Accepted: 07/09/2009] [Indexed: 10/20/2022] Open
Abstract
We report three experiments to test the possibilities reasoners think about when they understand a conditional of the form 'A only if B' compared to 'if A then B'. The experiments examine conditionals in the indicative mood (e.g., A occurred only if B occurred) and counterfactuals in the subjunctive mood (A would have occurred only if B had occurred). The first experiment examines the conjunctions of events that reasoners judge to be consistent with conditionals, e.g., A and B, not-A and not-B. It shows that people think about one possibility to understand 'if' and two possibilities to understand 'only if'; they think about two possibilities to understand counterfactual 'if' and 'only if'. The second experiment shows that the possibilities people think about when they understand 'only if' are in a different temporal order (e.g., B and A) to the possibilities they think about for 'if' (A and B). The third experiment shows that people make different inferences from 'only if' and 'if' conditionals and counterfactuals. The implications of the results for theories of counterfactual conditionals are considered.
Collapse
|
31
|
Abstract
We examined the comprehension of different types of conditionals. We measured the reading time of sentences primed by different types of conditionals (Experiments 1 and 2). We found that the participants read not-p and not-q faster when it was primed by the conditional form p if q and they were slower to read p and q when it was primed by the conditional form p only if q. This effect disappeared in the second experiment, where the order of the elements was reversed (q and p and not-q and not-p). These results suggest that the conditional form p if q elicits an initial representation "from p to q" with two possibilities, while the conditional form p only if q elicits a reverse representation with only one possibility. The third experiment showed that there were effects of the order only for the conditional if p then q, which confirms the reverse representation hypothesis. We discuss the implications of these results for different theories of conditional comprehension.
Collapse
|
32
|
|
33
|
Evans JSBT, Over DE, Handley SJ. Suppositions, extensionality, and conditionals: A critique of the mental model theory of Johnson-Laird and Byrne (2002). Psychol Rev 2005; 112:1040-52. [PMID: 16262481 DOI: 10.1037/0033-295x.112.4.1040] [Citation(s) in RCA: 63] [Impact Index Per Article: 3.3] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 11/08/2022]
Abstract
P. N. Johnson-Laird and R. M. J. Byrne proposed an influential theory of conditionals in which mental models represent logical possibilities and inferences are drawn from the extensions of possibilities that are used to represent conditionals. In this article, the authors argue that the extensional semantics underlying this theory is equivalent to that of the material, truth-functional conditional, at least for what they term "basic" conditionals, concerning arbitrary problem content. On the basis of both logical argument and psychological evidence, the authors propose that this approach is fundamentally mistaken and that conditionals must be viewed within a suppositional theory based on what philosophical logicians call the Ramsey test. The Johnson-Laird and Byrne theory is critically examined with respect to its account of basic conditionals, nonbasic conditionals, and counterfactuals.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Jonathan St B T Evans
- Centre for Thinking and Language, School of Psychology, University of Plymouth, Plymouth, England.
| | | | | |
Collapse
|
34
|
Schroyens W, Schaeken W, Handley S. In search of counter-examples: deductive rationality in human reasoning. THE QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY. A, HUMAN EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY 2003; 56:1129-45. [PMID: 12959907 DOI: 10.1080/02724980245000043] [Citation(s) in RCA: 35] [Impact Index Per Article: 1.7] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 10/26/2022]
Abstract
Dual-process theories come in many forms. They draw on the distinction between associative, heuristic, tacit, intuitive, or implicit processes (System 1) and rule-based, analytic, explicit processes (System 2). We present the results of contextual manipulations that have a bearing on the supposed primacy of System 1 (Stanovich & West, 2000). Experiment 1 showed that people who evaluated logically valid or invalid conditional inferences under a timing constraint (N=56), showed a smaller effect of logical validity than did people who were not placed under a timing constraint (N= 44). Experiment 2 similarly showed that stressing the logical constraint that only inferences that follow necessarily are to be endorsed (N = 36) increased the size of the validity effect, as compared to that of participants (N=33) given the standard instruction to make "logical" inferences. These findings concur with the thesis in dual-processing frameworks that "Rationality-2 processes" (Evans & Over, 1996), "test procedures" (Chater & Oaksford, 1999), or "conclusion validation processes" (Johnson-Laird & Byrne, 1991; Schroyens, Schaeken, & d'Ydewalle, 2001) serve to override the results of System 1 processes.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Walter Schroyens
- Department of Psychology, University of Leuven, Leuven, Belgium.
| | | | | |
Collapse
|
35
|
Dudley REJ, Over DE. People with delusions jump to conclusions: a theoretical account of research findings on the reasoning of people with delusions. Clin Psychol Psychother 2003. [DOI: 10.1002/cpp.376] [Citation(s) in RCA: 52] [Impact Index Per Article: 2.5] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 11/07/2022]
|
36
|
Simoneau M, Markovits H. Reasoning With Premises That Are Not Empirically True: Evidence for the Role of Inhibition and Retrieval. Dev Psychol 2003; 39:964-75. [PMID: 14584978 DOI: 10.1037/0012-1649.39.6.964] [Citation(s) in RCA: 46] [Impact Index Per Article: 2.2] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 11/08/2022]
Abstract
Two studies examined conditional reasoning with false premises. In Study 1, 12- and 16-year-old adolescents made "if-then" inferences after producing an alternative antecedent for the major premise. Older participants made more errors on the simple modus ponens inference than did younger ones. Reasoning with a false premise reduced this effect. Study 2 examined the relation between performance on a negative priming task (S. P. Tipper, 1985) and reasoning with contrary-to-fact premises in 9- and 11-year-olds. Overall, there was a correlation between the relative effect of negative priming on reaction times and the number of knowledge-based responses to the reasoning problems. The results of these studies are consistent with the idea that reasoning with premises that are not true requires an interaction between information retrieval and inhibition.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Michael Simoneau
- Departement de Psychologie, Université du Québec à Montréal, Montréal, Québec, Canada
| | | |
Collapse
|
37
|
García-Madruga JA, Gutiérrez F, Carriedo N, Moreno S, Johnson-Laird PN. Mental models in deductive reasoning. THE SPANISH JOURNAL OF PSYCHOLOGY 2002; 5:125-40. [PMID: 12428479 DOI: 10.1017/s1138741600005904] [Citation(s) in RCA: 8] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.4] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 11/06/2022]
Abstract
We report research investigating the role of mental models in deduction. The first study deals with conjunctive inferences (from one conjunction and two conditional premises) and disjunctive inferences (from one disjunction and the same two conditionals). The second study examines reasoning from multiple conditionals such as: If e then b; If a then b; If b then c; What follows between a and c? The third study addresses reasoning from different sorts of conditional assertions, including conditionals based on if then, only if, and unless. The paper also presents research on figural effects in syllogistic reasoning, on the effects of structure and believability in reasoning from double conditionals, and on reasoning from factual, counterfactual, and semifactual conditionals. The findings of these studies support the model theory, pose some difficulties for rule theories, and show the influence on reasoning of the linguistic structure and the semantic content of problems.
Collapse
|
38
|
Abstract
The authors outline a theory of conditionals of the form If A then C and If A then possibly C. The 2 sorts of conditional have separate core meanings that refer to sets of possibilities. Knowledge, pragmatics, and semantics can modulate these meanings. Modulation can add information about temporal and other relations between antecedent and consequent. It can also prevent the construction of possibilities to yield 10 distinct sets of possibilities to which conditionals can refer. The mental representation of a conditional normally makes explicit only the possibilities in which its antecedent is true, yielding other possibilities implicitly. Reasoners tend to focus on the explicit possibilities. The theory predicts the major phenomena of understanding and reasoning with conditionals.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- P N Johnson-Laird
- Department of Psychology, Princeton University, New Jersey 08544, USA.
| | | |
Collapse
|
39
|
Barrouillet P, Lecas JF. Content and context effects in children's and adults' conditional reasoning. THE QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY. A, HUMAN EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY 2002; 55:839-54. [PMID: 12188516 DOI: 10.1080/02724980143000587] [Citation(s) in RCA: 12] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.5] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 04/18/2023]
Abstract
We have recently shown that children interpret conditional sentences with binary terms (e.g., male/female) in both the antecedent and the consequent as biconditionals (Barrouillet & Lecas, 1998). We hypothesized that the same effect can be obtained with conditionals that do not contain binary terms provided that they are embedded in a context that restricts to only two the possible values on both the antecedent and the consequent. In the present experiment, we asked 12-year-old children, 15-year-old children, and adults to draw conclusions from conditional syllogisms that involved three types of conditional sentence: (1) conditionals with binary terms (BB), (2) conditionals with non-binary terms (NN), and (3) conditionals with non-binary terms embedded in a restrictive context (NNR). As we predicted, BB conditionals elicited more biconditional response patterns than did NN conditionals in all age groups. On the other hand, manipulating the context had the same effect in children but not in adults. Content and context constraints on conditional reasoning along with developmental issues are discussed within the framework of the mental models theory.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Pierre Barrouillet
- Université de Bourgogne, LEAD-CNRS, Faculté des Sciences Gabriel, Dijon, France.
| | | |
Collapse
|
40
|
Dieussaert K, Schaeken W, d’Ydewalle G. The Relative Contribution of Content and Context Factors on the Interpretation of Conditionals. Exp Psychol 2002. [DOI: 10.1026//1618-3169.49.3.181] [Citation(s) in RCA: 16] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.7] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 11/04/2022]
Abstract
Abstract. Previous research showed that conditional reasoning is affected by the content and the context of the studied problems. In this study, we investigate in detail the relative effect of three factors, namely the number of alternative or disabling reasons, speaker control, and pragmatic type, on the interpretation of conditionals. These factors were subject to prior research, but mostly in a fragmented way. This study indicates that some important nuances must be added to earlier findings. The number of alternatives and disablers, the speaker control, and the pragmatic type of conditional statements all have a considerable effect on how we interpret these sentences and reason with them, but they do not have equal weight. Alternatives/disablers play a significant but very limited role on the interpretation of conditionals, while the influence of speaker control and of pragmatic type is far more imperative.
Collapse
|
41
|
Markovits H, Quinn S. Efficiency of retrieval correlates with "logical" reasoning from causal conditional premises. Mem Cognit 2002; 30:696-706. [PMID: 12219887 DOI: 10.3758/bf03196426] [Citation(s) in RCA: 45] [Impact Index Per Article: 2.0] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 11/08/2022]
Abstract
In two experiments, we examined the prediction that there should be a relation between the speed with which subjects can retrieve potential causes for given effects and their reasoning with causal conditional premises (if cause P, then effect Q). It was also predicted that when subjects are given effects for which there exists a single strongly associated cause, speed of retrieval of a second potential cause should be particularly related to reasoning with invalid logical forms--namely, affirmation of the consequent and denial of the antecedent. In the first experiment, 49 university students were given both retrieval tasks and conditional reasoning problems. The results were generally consistent with the predictions. The second experiment, involving 57 university students, replicated the first, with some methodological variations. The results were also consistent with the predictions. An analysis of the combined results of the two experiments indicated that individual differences in efficiency of retrieval of information from long-term memory did predict performance on the invalid logical forms in the predicted ways. These results strongly support a retrieval model for conditional reasoning with causal premises.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Henry Markovits
- Département de Psychologie, University of Quebec, Montreal, Canada.
| | | |
Collapse
|
42
|
Dieussaert K, Schaeken W, d’Ydewalle G. The Relative Contribution of Content and Context Factors on the Interpretation of Conditionals. Exp Psychol 2002. [DOI: 10.1027//1618-3169.49.3.181] [Citation(s) in RCA: 0] [Impact Index Per Article: 0] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 11/23/2022]
|
43
|
|
44
|
|
45
|
Santamaría C, Espino O. Conditionals and directionality: on the meaning of if vs. only if. THE QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY. A, HUMAN EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY 2002; 55:41-57. [PMID: 11873854 DOI: 10.1080/02724980143000145] [Citation(s) in RCA: 17] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.8] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 10/17/2022]
Abstract
The aim of this study was to test the predictions of the current theories of reasoning about the comprehension of conditional statements. We used two types of conditional statement that are logically equivalent: if p then q and p only if q. The model theory of reasoning considers that these conditional forms differ in their initial meaning, because the negative contingency is considered only in the p only if q form. Mental-rule theories maintain that the interpretation of p only if q depends on a rephrasing of the statement as: if not q then not p. Alternatively, a directional bias may explain the differences between if p then q and p only if q. We report three experiments that demonstrate the existence of a directional bias in the comprehension of the conditionals. The results were not predicted by either the mental-rules theories or the model theory; they could, however, be easily assimilated by the model theory.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Carlos Santamaría
- Departamento de Psicología Cognitiva, Universidad de la Laguna, Tenerife, Spain.
| | | |
Collapse
|
46
|
Markovits H, Potvin F. Suppression of valid inferences and knowledge structures: the curious effect of producing alternative antecedents on reasoning with causal conditionals. Mem Cognit 2001; 29:736-44. [PMID: 11531228 DOI: 10.3758/bf03200476] [Citation(s) in RCA: 34] [Impact Index Per Article: 1.5] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 11/08/2022]
Abstract
These studies looked at the difficulty that reasoners have in accepting conditional ("If P then Q") major premises that are not necessarily true empirically, as a basis for deductive reasoning. Preliminary results have shown that when reasoners are asked to produce possible alternate antecedents to the major premise ("If A then Q"), they paradoxically tend to deny the modus ponens (MP) inference ("If P is true, then Q is true"). Three studies further explored these results. The first study gave university students paper-and-pencil tests in which instructions to "suppose that the major premise is true" was followed by a request to determine the next number in a sequence, to retrieve information unrelated to the premises, or to retrieve a possible case of "If A then Q." Relative to a control group, reasoners asked to produce an alternative antecedent showed a significant tendency to deny the MP inference, whereas no such tendency was observed for the two other tasks used. A second study compared performance on a condition in which reasoners were asked to produce an alternative antecedent with that when they were given an explicit alternative. Premises used in this study were such that the latter alternative antecedent was also spontaneously produced by over 70% of reasoners. Results showed that the tendency to refuse the MP premise could not be accounted for by the specific nature of the alternative produced. A third study found that the tendency to refuse the MP inference after producing an alternative antecedent was affected by the number of "disabling conditions" (i.e., conditions that allow "P to be true" and "Q to be false") available for the major premise. These results are interpreted as being consistent with a model that supposes that logical reasoning requires selective inhibition of real-world knowledge.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- H Markovits
- Department of Psychology, University of Quebec, Montreal, Canada.
| | | |
Collapse
|
47
|
Yang CY, Hwang SL. Reappraisal of Decision-Making Models in Engineering Applications. ACTA ACUST UNITED AC 2001. [DOI: 10.1207/s15327566ijce0502_5] [Citation(s) in RCA: 3] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.1] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 10/31/2022]
|
48
|
Schroyens WJ, Schaeken W, D'Ydewalle G. The processing of negations in conditional reasoning: A meta-analytic case study in mental model and/or mental logic theory. THINKING & REASONING 2001. [DOI: 10.1080/13546780042000091] [Citation(s) in RCA: 21] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.9] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 10/17/2022]
|
49
|
Meiser T, Klauer KC, Naumer B. Propositional reasoning and working memory: the role of prior training and pragmatic content. Acta Psychol (Amst) 2001; 106:303-27. [PMID: 11258120 DOI: 10.1016/s0001-6918(00)00055-x] [Citation(s) in RCA: 20] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.9] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 10/18/2022] Open
Abstract
Working memory involvement in propositional reasoning was explored after different kinds of training. The training conditions aimed to reduce the impact of non-analytic heuristics and to enhance analytic inference processes according to mental logic theories, the mental model theory, and the theory of pragmatic reasoning schemata. Following an initial training phase, secondary task interference was investigated using concurrent spatial tapping (Experiment 1), random number generation (Experiment 2), and articulatory suppression (Experiment 3). A training condition practicing the construction and use of mental models via a truth table task increased the disruption of reasoning performance by random number generation and articulatory suppression, whereas the other training conditions did not affect susceptibility to secondary task interference. The results corroborate implications of the mental model theory of reasoning.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- T Meiser
- School of Psychology, Cardiff University, UK.
| | | | | |
Collapse
|
50
|
Abstract
This paper develops a theory of how interpretative processes constrain inferential performance on conditional reasoning tasks. Experiment 1 investigated the hypothesis that performance on common reasoning tasks is mediated by different interpretive variables. Necessity and sufficiency relations predicted performance on the conditional arguments task, whereas on the Wason task, performance was predicted by whether the conditional statement instantiated a deontic or a factual relation. Performance on the truth-table task was predicted by both sets of variables. Experiment 2 explored the mapping relation between interpretation, representation, and inference. It was observed that conditional responses to the Wason and arguments tasks were based on different representations of the conditional relationship. These data rule out a simple model of the interplay between interpretation and reasoning in which the interpretation of a statement is driven solely by its content, and instead, indicate that the interpretation of conditional relations is task-specific.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- V A Thompson
- University of Saskatchewan, 9 Campus Drive, SK, S7N 5A5, Saskatoon, Canada.
| |
Collapse
|