1
|
Johnson-Laird PN, Ragni M. Reasoning about possibilities: Modal logics, possible worlds, and mental models. Psychon Bull Rev 2024:10.3758/s13423-024-02518-z. [PMID: 39012580 DOI: 10.3758/s13423-024-02518-z] [Citation(s) in RCA: 0] [Impact Index Per Article: 0] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Accepted: 04/19/2024] [Indexed: 07/17/2024]
Abstract
Everyone reasons about possibilities. This article explains how they could do so using mental models. The theory makes four major claims: 1. Correct inferences are necessary, referring only to facts or possibilities to which the premises refer and not ruling any of them out, for example: She left or hid; Therefore, it's possible that she left and possible that she hid. 2. A possibility such as that she hid, which is represented in an intuitive model, presupposes the possibility that it did not occur, she did not hide, which, if reasoners deliberate, is represented in the resulting model. 3. Reasoners condense consistent possibilities, such as the earlier pair, into one possibility: it is possible that she left and she hid. 4. Inconsistencies, such as she left or hid, and she neither left nor hid, refer to no possibilities whatsoever - they have an empty model - and so their only effects are local. Hence, any inference can be withdrawn with impunity if there is knowledge to the contrary. Experiments have corroborated each of these principles. They are incompatible with four essentials of standard modal logics, which concern deductions based on "possible" or "necessary". Their formal deductions correspond to valid inferences, which have no counterexamples in which the premises are true but the conclusion is false. And so the article examines the differences between the two approaches, and explores the adaptation of a modal logic to account for correct human reasoning. Its feasibility is an open question.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- P N Johnson-Laird
- Department of Psychology, Princeton University, Princeton, NJ, 08540, USA
- Department of Psychology, New York University, 6 Washington Place, New York, NY, 10003, USA
| | - Marco Ragni
- Technische Universität Chemnitz, Thüringer Weg 11, 09126, Chemnitz, Germany.
| |
Collapse
|
2
|
Skovgaard-Olsen N, Collins P, Klauer KC. Possible worlds truth table task. Cognition 2023; 238:105507. [PMID: 37331324 DOI: 10.1016/j.cognition.2023.105507] [Citation(s) in RCA: 0] [Impact Index Per Article: 0] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 04/28/2022] [Revised: 05/26/2023] [Accepted: 05/30/2023] [Indexed: 06/20/2023]
Abstract
In this paper, a novel experimental task is developed for testing the highly influential, but experimentally underexplored, possible worlds account of conditionals (Lewis, 1973; Stalnaker, 1968). In Experiment 1, this new task is used to test both indicative and subjunctive conditionals. For indicative conditionals, five competing truth tables are compared, including the previously untested, multi-dimensional possible worlds semantics of Bradley (2012). In Experiment 2, these results are replicated and it is shown that they cannot be accounted for by an alternative hypothesis proposed by our reviewers. In Experiment 3, individual variation in truth assignments of indicative conditionals is investigated via Bayesian mixture models that classify participants as following one of several competing truth tables. As a novelty of this study, it is found that a possible worlds semantics of Lewis and Stalnaker is capable of accounting for participants' aggregate truth value assignments in this task. Applied to indicative conditionals, we show across three experiments, that the theory both captures participants' truth values at the aggregate level (Experiments 1 and 2) and that it makes up the largest subgroup in the analysis of individual variation in our experimental paradigm (Experiment 3).
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
| | - Peter Collins
- School of Human Sciences, University of Greenwich, UK
| | | |
Collapse
|
3
|
Collins PJ, Krzyżanowska K, Hartmann S, Wheeler G, Hahn U. Conditionals and testimony. Cogn Psychol 2020; 122:101329. [PMID: 32805584 DOI: 10.1016/j.cogpsych.2020.101329] [Citation(s) in RCA: 4] [Impact Index Per Article: 1.0] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 07/31/2018] [Revised: 06/02/2020] [Accepted: 06/21/2020] [Indexed: 11/16/2022]
Abstract
Conditionals and conditional reasoning have been a long-standing focus of research across a number of disciplines, ranging from psychology through linguistics to philosophy. But almost no work has concerned itself with the question of how hearing or reading a conditional changes our beliefs. Given that we acquire much-perhaps most-of what we believe through the testimony of others, the simple matter of acquiring conditionals via others' assertion of a conditional seems integral to any full understanding of the conditional and conditional reasoning. In this paper we detail a number of basic intuitions about how beliefs might change in response to a conditional being uttered, and show how these are backed by behavioral data. In the remainder of the paper, we then show how these deceptively simple phenomena pose a fundamental challenge to present theoretical accounts of the conditional and conditional reasoning - a challenge which no account presently fully meets.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Peter J Collins
- Dept. of Psychological Sciences, Birkbeck, Univ. of London, United Kingdom; Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy, LMU Munich, Germany.
| | - Karolina Krzyżanowska
- Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy, LMU Munich, Germany; Institute for Logic, Language and Computation, University of Amsterdam, Netherlands; Arché Research Centre, University of St Andrew's, United Kingdom.
| | | | | | - Ulrike Hahn
- Dept. of Psychological Sciences, Birkbeck, Univ. of London, United Kingdom; Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy, LMU Munich, Germany
| |
Collapse
|
4
|
Abstract
Conditionals statements are a common and necessary component in natural languages. The research reported in this paper is on a fundamental question about singular conditionals. Is there an adequate account of people's truth, falsity, and credibility (probability) judgments about these conditionals when their antecedents are false? Two experiments examined people's quantitative credibility ratings and qualitative truth and falsity judgments for singular conditionals, if p then q, given false antecedent, not-p, cases. The results demonstrate that, when relevant knowledge about the conditional probability of q given p, P(q|p), is available to participants in not-p cases, they tend to make credibility ratings based on P(q|p), and to make "true" (or "false") judgments at a high (or low) level of these credibility ratings. These findings favor the Jeffrey table account of these conditionals over the other existing accounts, including that of the de Finetti table.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Moyun Wang
- 1 School of Psychology, Shaanxi Key Laboratory of Behavior and Cognitive Neuroscience, Shaanxi Normal University, Xi'an, PR China
| | - Mingyi Zhu
- 1 School of Psychology, Shaanxi Key Laboratory of Behavior and Cognitive Neuroscience, Shaanxi Normal University, Xi'an, PR China
| |
Collapse
|
5
|
Goodwin GP, Johnson-Laird PN. The Truth of Conditional Assertions. Cogn Sci 2018; 42:2502-2533. [PMID: 30159915 DOI: 10.1111/cogs.12666] [Citation(s) in RCA: 4] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.7] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 03/17/2015] [Revised: 06/15/2018] [Accepted: 06/21/2018] [Indexed: 11/28/2022]
Abstract
Given a basic conditional of the form, If A then C, individuals usually list three cases as possible: A and C, not-A and not-C, not-A and C. This result corroborates the theory of mental models. By contrast, individuals often judge that the conditional is true only in the case of A and C, and that cases of not-A are irrelevant to its truth or falsity. This result corroborates other theories of conditionals. To resolve the discrepancy, we devised two new tasks: the "collective" truth task, in which participants judged whether sets of assertions about a specific individual, such as: If A then C, not-A, C, could all be true at the same time; and one in which participants judged the truth of conditional predictions about specific future events. The results consistently matched the three possibilities, thereby corroborating the model theory. They also showed a massive violation of the probability calculus in estimates of the probabilities of the four cases in the partition of conditionals (A and C, A and not-C, not-A and C, and not-A and not-C), which summed to over 200%.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
| | - P N Johnson-Laird
- Department of Psychology, Princeton University.,Department of Psychology, New York University
| |
Collapse
|
6
|
Nakamura H, Shao J, Baratgin J, Over DE, Takahashi T, Yama H. Understanding Conditionals in the East: A Replication Study of With Easterners. Front Psychol 2018; 9:505. [PMID: 29706913 PMCID: PMC5907311 DOI: 10.3389/fpsyg.2018.00505] [Citation(s) in RCA: 4] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.7] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Download PDF] [Figures] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 11/06/2017] [Accepted: 03/26/2018] [Indexed: 11/16/2022] Open
Abstract
The new probabilistic approaches to the natural language conditional imply that there is a parallel relation between indicative conditionals (ICs) “if s then b” and conditional bets (CBs) “I bet $1 that if s then b” in two aspects. First, the probability of an IC and the probability of winning a CB are both the conditional probability, P(s|b). Second, both an IC and a CB have a third value “void” (neither true nor false, neither wins nor loses) when the antecedent is false (¬s). These aspects of the parallel relation have been found in Western participants. In the present study, we investigated whether this parallel is also present in Eastern participants. We replicated the study of Politzer et al. (2010) with Chinese and Japanese participants and made two predictions. First, Eastern participants will tend to engage in more holistic cognition and take all possible cases, including ¬s, into account when they judge the probability of conditional: Easterners may assess the probability of antecedent s out of all possible cases, P(s), and then may focus on consequent b out of s, P(b|s). Consequently, Easterners may judge the probability of the conditional, and of winning the bet, to be P(s) ∗ P(b|s) = P(s & b), and false/losing the bet as P(s) ∗ P(¬b|s) = P(s & ¬b). Second, Eastern participants will tend to be strongly affected by context, and they may not show parallel relationships between ICs and CBs. The results indicate no cultural differences in judging the false antecedent cases: Eastern participants judged false antecedent cases as not making the IC true nor false and as not being winning or losing outcomes. However, there were cultural differences when asked about the probability of a conditional. Consistent with our hypothesis, Eastern participants had a greater tendency to take all possible cases into account, especially in CBs. We discuss whether these results can be explained by a hypothesized tendency for Eastern people to think in more holistic and context-dependent terms than Western people.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Hiroko Nakamura
- Department of Human Informatics, Aichi Shukutoku University, Nagakute, Japan
| | - Jing Shao
- CHArt (PARIS), Université Paris 8 and EPHE, Saint-Denis, France.,Université de Haute-Alsace, Mulhouse, France
| | - Jean Baratgin
- CHArt (PARIS), Université Paris 8 and EPHE, Saint-Denis, France.,Institut Jean Nicod, École Normale Supérieure, Paris, France
| | - David E Over
- Department of Psychology, Durham University, Durham, United Kingdom
| | - Tatsuji Takahashi
- School of Science and Engineering, Tokyo Denki University, Tokyo, Japan
| | - Hiroshi Yama
- Faculty of Literature and Human Sciences, Osaka City University, Osaka, Japan
| |
Collapse
|
7
|
Douven I, Elqayam S, Singmann H, van Wijnbergen-Huitink J. Conditionals and inferential connections: A hypothetical inferential theory. Cogn Psychol 2018; 101:50-81. [DOI: 10.1016/j.cogpsych.2017.09.002] [Citation(s) in RCA: 23] [Impact Index Per Article: 3.8] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 10/19/2016] [Revised: 09/12/2017] [Accepted: 09/25/2017] [Indexed: 10/18/2022]
|
8
|
Affiliation(s)
- Moyun Wang
- Shaanxi Key Laboratory of Behavior and Cognitive Neuroscience, School of Psychology, Shaanxi Normal University, Xi'an, China
| | - Pengfei Yin
- Shaanxi Key Laboratory of Behavior and Cognitive Neuroscience, School of Psychology, Shaanxi Normal University, Xi'an, China
| | - Liyuan Zheng
- Shaanxi Key Laboratory of Behavior and Cognitive Neuroscience, School of Psychology, Shaanxi Normal University, Xi'an, China
| |
Collapse
|
9
|
Wang M, Yao X. The dual reading of general conditionals: The influence of abstract versus concrete contexts. Q J Exp Psychol (Hove) 2018; 71:859-869. [PMID: 28278574 DOI: 10.1080/17470218.2017.1281321] [Citation(s) in RCA: 2] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.3] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 10/19/2022]
Abstract
A current main issue on conditionals is whether the meaning of general conditionals (e.g., If a card is red, then it is round) is deterministic (exceptionless) or probabilistic (exception-tolerating). In order to resolve the issue, two experiments examined the influence of conditional contexts (with vs. without frequency information of truth table cases) on the reading of general conditionals. Experiment 1 examined the direct reading of general conditionals in the possibility judgment task. Experiment 2 examined the indirect reading of general conditionals in the truth judgment task. It was found that both the direct and indirect reading of general conditionals exhibited the duality: the predominant deterministic semantic reading of conditionals without frequency information, and the predominant probabilistic pragmatic reading of conditionals with frequency information. The context of general conditionals determined the predominant reading of general conditionals. There were obvious individual differences in reading general conditionals with frequency information. The meaning of general conditionals is relative, depending on conditional contexts. The reading of general conditionals is flexible and complex so that no simple deterministic and probabilistic accounts are able to explain it. The present findings are beyond the extant deterministic and probabilistic accounts of conditionals.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Moyun Wang
- School of Psychology, Shaanxi Key Laboratory of Behavior and Cognitive Neuroscience, Shaanxi Normal University, Xi'an, China
| | - Xinyun Yao
- School of Psychology, Shaanxi Key Laboratory of Behavior and Cognitive Neuroscience, Shaanxi Normal University, Xi'an, China
| |
Collapse
|
10
|
Abstract
To adjudicate between deterministic and probabilistic accounts of the meaning of conditionals, we examined the influence of context on the reading of general conditionals. Context was varied with the contrast context, where participants judged uncertain conditionals after certain conditionals, and the control context, where participants judged only uncertain conditionals. Experiment 1 had participants to judge whether a set of truth table cases was possible for the conditional. Experiment 2 had participants to judge whether the conditional was true for a set of truth table cases. The findings are as follows. Possibility and truth judgments showed a similar response pattern. The reading of general conditionals varied with conditional contexts. The predominant reading was deterministic in the contrast context but was probabilistic in the control context. Conditional contexts yielded a significant contrast effect. Meanwhile, conditional probability P( q| p) made a smaller difference to the acceptance rate in the contrast context than in the control context. The overall pattern is beyond both the deterministic and probabilistic accounts. Alternatively, we propose a dynamic-threshold account for the relative reading of general conditionals.
Collapse
|
11
|
Skovgaard-Olsen N, Kellen D, Krahl H, Klauer KC. Relevance differently affects the truth, acceptability, and probability evaluations of “and”, “but”, “therefore”, and “if–then”. THINKING & REASONING 2017. [DOI: 10.1080/13546783.2017.1374306] [Citation(s) in RCA: 8] [Impact Index Per Article: 1.1] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 10/18/2022]
Affiliation(s)
- Niels Skovgaard-Olsen
- Department of Philosophy, University of Konstanz, Konstanz, Germany
- Department of Psychology, Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg, Freiburg, Germany
| | - David Kellen
- Department of Psychology, Syracuse University, Syracuse, NY, USA
| | - Hannes Krahl
- Department of Psychology, University of Chemnitz, Chemnitz, Germany
| | | |
Collapse
|
12
|
Sevenants A, Dieussaert K, Schaeken W. Truth table task: Working memory load, latencies, and perceived relevance. JOURNAL OF COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY 2013. [DOI: 10.1080/20445911.2013.775131] [Citation(s) in RCA: 3] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.3] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 10/27/2022]
|
13
|
Santamaría C, Tse PP, Moreno-Ríos S, García-Madruga JA. Deductive reasoning and metalogical knowledge in preadolescence: A mental model appraisal. JOURNAL OF COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY 2013. [DOI: 10.1080/20445911.2012.743988] [Citation(s) in RCA: 7] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.6] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 10/27/2022]
|
14
|
|
15
|
Sevenants A, Dieussaert K, Schaeken W. Truth table tasks: Irrelevance and cognitive ability. THINKING & REASONING 2011. [DOI: 10.1080/13546783.2011.569153] [Citation(s) in RCA: 6] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.5] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 10/18/2022]
|
16
|
General aptitude and the assumption of truth in deductively rational reasoning about probable but false antecedent to consequent relations. Adv Cogn Psychol 2010; 6:88-102. [PMID: 21228921 PMCID: PMC3019985 DOI: 10.2478/v10053-008-0079-z] [Citation(s) in RCA: 1] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.1] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Download PDF] [Figures] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 09/08/2009] [Accepted: 09/01/2010] [Indexed: 11/20/2022] Open
Abstract
Two experiments (N1 = 117 and
N2 = 245) on reasoning with knowledge-rich
conditionals showed a main effect of logical validity, which was due to the
negative effect of counter-examples being smaller for valid than for invalid
arguments. These findings support the thesis that some people tend to inhibit
background inconsistent with the hypothetical truth of the premises, while
others tend to abandon the implicit truth-assumption when they have factual
evidence to the contrary. Findings show that adhering to the truth-assumption in
the face of conflicting evidence to the contrary requires an investment of time
and effort which people with a higher general aptitude are more likely to
do.
Collapse
|
17
|
Schroyens W, Braem S. The initial representation in reasoning towards an interpretation of conditional sentences. Q J Exp Psychol (Hove) 2010; 64:339-62. [PMID: 21104563 DOI: 10.1080/17470218.2010.513734] [Citation(s) in RCA: 3] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.2] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 10/18/2022]
Abstract
All accounts of human reasoning (whether presented at the symbolic or subsymbolic level) have to reckon with the temporal organization of the human processing systems and the ephemeral nature of the representations it uses. We present three new empirical tests for the hypothesis that people commence the interpretational process by constructing a minimal initial representation. In the case of if A then C the initial representation captures the occurrence of the consequent, C, within the context of the antecedent, A. Conditional inference problems are created by a categorical premise that affirms or denies A or C. The initial representation allows an inference when the explicitly represented information matches (e.g., the categorical premise A affirms the antecedent "A") but not when it mismatches (e.g., "not-A" denies A). Experiments 1 and 2 confirmed that people tend to accept the conclusion that "nothing follows" for the denial problems, as indeed they do not have a determinate initial-model conclusion. Experiment 3 demonstrated the other way round that the effect of problem type (affirmation versus denial) is reduced when we impede the possibility of inferring a determinate conclusion on the basis of the initial representation of both the affirmation and the denial problems.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Walter Schroyens
- Laboratory of Experimental Psychology, University of Leuven, Leuven, Belgium.
| | | |
Collapse
|