1
|
Peng Z, Apfelbacher C, Brandstetter S, Eils R, Kabesch M, Lehmann I, Trump S, Wellmann S, Genuneit J. Directed acyclic graph for epidemiological studies in childhood food allergy: Construction, user's guide, and application. Allergy 2024. [PMID: 38234010 DOI: 10.1111/all.16025] [Citation(s) in RCA: 0] [Impact Index Per Article: 0] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Grants] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 06/21/2023] [Revised: 11/28/2023] [Accepted: 01/05/2024] [Indexed: 01/19/2024]
Abstract
Understanding modifiable prenatal and early life causal determinants of food allergy is important for the prevention of the disease. Randomized clinical trials studying environmental and dietary determinants of food allergy may not always be feasible. Identifying risk/protective factors for early-life food allergy often relies on observational studies, which may be affected by confounding bias. The directed acyclic graph (DAG) is a causal diagram useful to guide causal inference from observational epidemiological research. To date, research on food allergy has made little use of this promising method. We performed a literature review of existing evidence with a systematic search, synthesized 32 known risk/protective factors, and constructed a comprehensive DAG for early-life food allergy development. We present an easy-to-use online tool for researchers to re-construct, amend, and modify the DAG along with a user's guide to minimize confounding bias. We estimated that adjustment strategies in 57% of previous observational studies on modifiable factors of childhood food allergy could be improved if the researchers determined their adjustment sets by DAG. Future researchers who are interested in the causal inference of food allergy development in early life can apply the DAG to identify covariates that should and should not be controlled in observational studies.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Zhuoxin Peng
- Pediatric Epidemiology, Department of Pediatrics, Medical Faculty, Leipzig University, Leipzig, Germany
| | - Christian Apfelbacher
- Institute of Social Medicine and Health Systems Research, Otto von Guericke University Magdeburg, Magdeburg, Germany
| | - Susanne Brandstetter
- Member of the Research and Development Campus Regensburg (WECARE) at the Clinic St. Hedwig, Regensburg, Germany
- University Children's Hospital Regensburg (KUNO-Clinics), University of Regensburg, Clinic St. Hedwig, Regensburg, Germany
| | - Roland Eils
- Center for Digital Health, Berlin Institute of Health (BIH) at Charité-Universitatsmedizin Berlin, Corporate member of Freie Universität Berlin, Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin, Berlin, Germany
- German Center for Lung Research (DZL), Associated Partner Site, Berlin, Germany
- German Center of Child and Youth Health (DZKJ), Germany
| | - Michael Kabesch
- Member of the Research and Development Campus Regensburg (WECARE) at the Clinic St. Hedwig, Regensburg, Germany
- University Children's Hospital Regensburg (KUNO-Clinics), University of Regensburg, Clinic St. Hedwig, Regensburg, Germany
| | - Irina Lehmann
- German Center for Lung Research (DZL), Associated Partner Site, Berlin, Germany
- German Center of Child and Youth Health (DZKJ), Germany
- Molecular Epidemiology Unit, Berlin Institute of Health at Charité-Universitätsmedizin Berlin, Berlin, Germany
| | - Saskia Trump
- Molecular Epidemiology Unit, Berlin Institute of Health at Charité-Universitätsmedizin Berlin, Berlin, Germany
| | - Sven Wellmann
- Department of Neonatology, University Children's Hospital Regensburg (KUNO), Hospital St. Hedwig of the Order of St. John, University of Regensburg, Regensburg, Germany
| | - Jon Genuneit
- Pediatric Epidemiology, Department of Pediatrics, Medical Faculty, Leipzig University, Leipzig, Germany
- German Center of Child and Youth Health (DZKJ), Germany
| |
Collapse
|
2
|
Weed DL. Commentary: On the reliability of causal claims. GLOBAL EPIDEMIOLOGY 2022; 4:100087. [PMID: 37637015 PMCID: PMC10445962 DOI: 10.1016/j.gloepi.2022.100087] [Citation(s) in RCA: 1] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.3] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 08/13/2022] [Revised: 10/12/2022] [Accepted: 10/14/2022] [Indexed: 11/05/2022] Open
Abstract
Causal assessments in epidemiology are a complex process due to the many methods involved. The general scientific method lords over the process joined by study designs and statistical methods. Other methods include those that evaluate quality and bias along with the research synthesis methods such as the systematic narrative review, meta-analysis, and the criteria-based methods. When different investigators apply these methods to the same evidence and come up with different causal assessments, as described in the review by Goodman et al. in this issue, a key question becomes, how can the differences be explained? A prime candidate involves different methodologic choices. A deeper question emerges from this same situation: are the methods used for causal assessments reliable? Reliability is a hallmark of scientific practice. The methods used to make claims about causality should be reliable. Given the complexity of the causal assessment process, an objective evaluation of reliability is challenging but clearly worth the effort. Fortunately, Hill's criterion of analogy, much maligned in epidemiology, provides a clue. This commentary explores the issue of the reliability of causal claims using the Goodman et al. systematic review as its foil along with the claims by EPA, IARC, and ATSDR about the relationship between perchloroethylene and non-Hodgkin lymphoma, the claims Goodman et al. believe are wrong.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Douglas L. Weed
- DLW Consulting Services, LLC, 1302 North Oak Forest Rd., Salt Lake City, UT 84103, USA
| |
Collapse
|
3
|
Koterov AN, Ushenkova LN, Biryukov AP. Hill’s Criterion ‘Experiment’: The Counterfactual Approach in Non-Radiation and Radiation Sciences. BIOL BULL+ 2022. [DOI: 10.1134/s1062359021120062] [Citation(s) in RCA: 0] [Impact Index Per Article: 0] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 11/23/2022]
|
4
|
Shimonovich M, Pearce A, Thomson H, Keyes K, Katikireddi SV. Assessing causality in epidemiology: revisiting Bradford Hill to incorporate developments in causal thinking. Eur J Epidemiol 2021; 36:873-887. [PMID: 33324996 PMCID: PMC8206235 DOI: 10.1007/s10654-020-00703-7] [Citation(s) in RCA: 63] [Impact Index Per Article: 15.8] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [MESH Headings] [Grants] [Track Full Text] [Download PDF] [Figures] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 06/23/2020] [Accepted: 12/02/2020] [Indexed: 01/08/2023]
Abstract
The nine Bradford Hill (BH) viewpoints (sometimes referred to as criteria) are commonly used to assess causality within epidemiology. However, causal thinking has since developed, with three of the most prominent approaches implicitly or explicitly building on the potential outcomes framework: directed acyclic graphs (DAGs), sufficient-component cause models (SCC models, also referred to as 'causal pies') and the grading of recommendations, assessment, development and evaluation (GRADE) methodology. This paper explores how these approaches relate to BH's viewpoints and considers implications for improving causal assessment. We mapped the three approaches above against each BH viewpoint. We found overlap across the approaches and BH viewpoints, underscoring BH viewpoints' enduring importance. Mapping the approaches helped elucidate the theoretical underpinning of each viewpoint and articulate the conditions when the viewpoint would be relevant. Our comparisons identified commonality on four viewpoints: strength of association (including analysis of plausible confounding); temporality; plausibility (encoded by DAGs or SCC models to articulate mediation and interaction, respectively); and experiments (including implications of study design on exchangeability). Consistency may be more usefully operationalised by considering an effect size's transportability to a different population or unexplained inconsistency in effect sizes (statistical heterogeneity). Because specificity rarely occurs, falsification exposures or outcomes (i.e., negative controls) may be more useful. The presence of a dose-response relationship may be less than widely perceived as it can easily arise from confounding. We found limited utility for coherence and analogy. This study highlights a need for greater clarity on BH viewpoints to improve causal assessment.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Michal Shimonovich
- MRC/CSO Social and Public Health Sciences Unit, University of Glasgow, Glasgow, UK.
| | - Anna Pearce
- MRC/CSO Social and Public Health Sciences Unit, University of Glasgow, Glasgow, UK
| | - Hilary Thomson
- MRC/CSO Social and Public Health Sciences Unit, University of Glasgow, Glasgow, UK
| | - Katherine Keyes
- Mailman School of Public Health, Columbia University, New York, NY, USA
| | | |
Collapse
|
5
|
Shimonovich M, Pearce A, Thomson H, Keyes K, Katikireddi SV. Assessing causality in epidemiology: revisiting Bradford Hill to incorporate developments in causal thinking. Eur J Epidemiol 2021. [PMID: 33324996 DOI: 10.1007/s10654-020-00703-7/tables/5] [Citation(s) in RCA: 1] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.3] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [MESH Headings] [Grants] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 03/26/2023]
Abstract
The nine Bradford Hill (BH) viewpoints (sometimes referred to as criteria) are commonly used to assess causality within epidemiology. However, causal thinking has since developed, with three of the most prominent approaches implicitly or explicitly building on the potential outcomes framework: directed acyclic graphs (DAGs), sufficient-component cause models (SCC models, also referred to as 'causal pies') and the grading of recommendations, assessment, development and evaluation (GRADE) methodology. This paper explores how these approaches relate to BH's viewpoints and considers implications for improving causal assessment. We mapped the three approaches above against each BH viewpoint. We found overlap across the approaches and BH viewpoints, underscoring BH viewpoints' enduring importance. Mapping the approaches helped elucidate the theoretical underpinning of each viewpoint and articulate the conditions when the viewpoint would be relevant. Our comparisons identified commonality on four viewpoints: strength of association (including analysis of plausible confounding); temporality; plausibility (encoded by DAGs or SCC models to articulate mediation and interaction, respectively); and experiments (including implications of study design on exchangeability). Consistency may be more usefully operationalised by considering an effect size's transportability to a different population or unexplained inconsistency in effect sizes (statistical heterogeneity). Because specificity rarely occurs, falsification exposures or outcomes (i.e., negative controls) may be more useful. The presence of a dose-response relationship may be less than widely perceived as it can easily arise from confounding. We found limited utility for coherence and analogy. This study highlights a need for greater clarity on BH viewpoints to improve causal assessment.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Michal Shimonovich
- MRC/CSO Social and Public Health Sciences Unit, University of Glasgow, Glasgow, UK.
| | - Anna Pearce
- MRC/CSO Social and Public Health Sciences Unit, University of Glasgow, Glasgow, UK
| | - Hilary Thomson
- MRC/CSO Social and Public Health Sciences Unit, University of Glasgow, Glasgow, UK
| | - Katherine Keyes
- Mailman School of Public Health, Columbia University, New York, NY, USA
| | | |
Collapse
|
6
|
Koterov AN, Ushenkova LN, Biryukov AP. Hill’s Temporality Criterion: Reverse Causation and Its Radiation Aspect. BIOL BULL+ 2021. [DOI: 10.1134/s1062359020120031] [Citation(s) in RCA: 2] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.5] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 01/21/2023]
|
7
|
Meilia PDI, Zeegers MP, Herkutanto, Freeman M. INFERENCE: An Evidence-Based Approach for Medicolegal Causal Analyses. INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF ENVIRONMENTAL RESEARCH AND PUBLIC HEALTH 2020; 17:E8353. [PMID: 33187384 PMCID: PMC7697841 DOI: 10.3390/ijerph17228353] [Citation(s) in RCA: 3] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.6] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Download PDF] [Figures] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 09/11/2020] [Revised: 11/09/2020] [Accepted: 11/10/2020] [Indexed: 11/16/2022]
Abstract
A fundamental purpose of forensic medical, or medicolegal, analysis is to provide legal factfinders with an opinion regarding the causal relationship between an alleged unlawful or negligent action and a medically observed adverse outcome, which is needed to establish legal liability. At present, there are no universally established standards for medicolegal causal analysis, although several different approaches to causation exist, with varying strengths and weaknesses and degrees of practical utility. These approaches can be categorized as intuitive or probabilistic, which are distributed along a spectrum of increasing case complexity. This paper proposes a systematic approach to evidence-based assessment of causation in forensic medicine, called the INtegration of Forensic Epidemiology and the Rigorous EvaluatioN of Causation Elements (INFERENCE) approach. The INFERENCE approach is an evolution of existing causal analysis methods and consists of a stepwise method of increasing complexity. We aimed to develop a probabilistic causal analysis approach that (1) fits the needs of legal factfinders who require an estimate of the probability of causation, and (2) is still sufficiently straightforward to be applied in real-world forensic medical practice. As the INFERENCE approach is most relevant in complex cases, we also propose a process for selecting the most appropriate causal analysis method for any given case. The goal of this approach is to improve the reproducibility and transparency of causal analyses, which will promote evidence-based practice and quality assurance in forensic medicine, resulting in expert opinions that are reliable and objective in legal proceedings.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Putri Dianita Ika Meilia
- Care and Public Health Research Institute (CAPHRI), Faculty of Health, Medicine and Life Sciences, Maastricht University Medical Center+, Universiteitssingel 40, 6229 ER Maastricht, The Netherlands; (M.P.Z.); (M.F.)
| | - Maurice P. Zeegers
- Care and Public Health Research Institute (CAPHRI), Faculty of Health, Medicine and Life Sciences, Maastricht University Medical Center+, Universiteitssingel 40, 6229 ER Maastricht, The Netherlands; (M.P.Z.); (M.F.)
| | - Herkutanto
- Department of Forensic Medicine and Medicolegal Studies, Faculty of Medicine, University of Indonesia, Jl. Salemba Raya No. 4, Salemba, Jakarta Pusat 10430, Indonesia;
| | - Michael Freeman
- Care and Public Health Research Institute (CAPHRI), Faculty of Health, Medicine and Life Sciences, Maastricht University Medical Center+, Universiteitssingel 40, 6229 ER Maastricht, The Netherlands; (M.P.Z.); (M.F.)
| |
Collapse
|
8
|
Dragani TA. Difficulties in establishing a causal link between chemical exposures and cancer cannot be overcome by court assessments. Hum Exp Toxicol 2020; 39:1095-1107. [PMID: 32153198 DOI: 10.1177/0960327120911426] [Citation(s) in RCA: 3] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.6] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 12/14/2022]
Abstract
Scientific data are often used in lawsuits to prove, or dismiss, causation by a claimed factor of a claimed disease. Recent media reports of million-dollar compensations awarded to some cancer patients who had been exposed to certain chemical substances motivated me to examine how solid the causal links really were. Here, I discuss the limitations of epidemiological research on cancer causation and highlight how new knowledge of cancer genetics makes it unrealistic to expect that cancer causation can be clearly demonstrated. I then present two exposure-cancer cases, namely talcum powder-ovarian cancer and glyphosate-non-Hodgkin lymphoma, that led to civil lawsuits decided, in the United States, in favor of the claimants. Both these cancers have several risk factors, among which the claimed exposure presents only a minor, if any, increased risk. Through these cases, I explain why the use of epidemiological data is inappropriate to define causal associations in complex diseases like cancer. I close by suggesting a fairer approach, called proportional liability, to resolving future cancer litigation cases.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- T A Dragani
- Department of Research, Fondazione IRCCS Istituto Nazionale dei Tumori, Milan, Italy
| |
Collapse
|
9
|
McLinden T. Which is the cart and which is the horse? Getting more out of cross-sectional epidemiological studies. Public Health Nutr 2019; 22:1-3. [PMID: 30990156 PMCID: PMC10260562 DOI: 10.1017/s1368980019000624] [Citation(s) in RCA: 0] [Impact Index Per Article: 0] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 11/07/2022]
Affiliation(s)
- Taylor McLinden
- British Columbia Centre for Excellence in HIV/AIDS608-1081 Burrard StreetVancouver,BC,Canada,V6Z 1Y6
| |
Collapse
|
10
|
Olsen J, Jensen UJ. Causal criteria: time has come for a revision. Eur J Epidemiol 2019; 34:537-541. [PMID: 30649703 DOI: 10.1007/s10654-018-00479-x] [Citation(s) in RCA: 14] [Impact Index Per Article: 2.3] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 07/31/2018] [Accepted: 12/26/2018] [Indexed: 12/26/2022]
Abstract
Epidemiologists study associations but they are usually interested in causation that could lead to disease prevention. Experience show, however, that many of the associations we identify are not the causes we take an interest in (correlation is not causation). In order to proper translate association into causes, a set of causal criteria was developed 50-60 years ago and they became important tools guiding this translational process (sometimes correlation is causation). Best known of these are the Bradford Hill 'criteria'. In these last 50 years, epidemiologic theory and infrastructure have advanced rapidly without changes in these causal criteria. We think time has come to revisit the 'old' criteria to see which ones we should keep and which ones should be taken out or be replaced by new measures of association. Robustness of these criteria in attempts to make the association go away should have high priority. A group of renowned internationally recognized researchers should have this task. Since classifying associations as causes is often done in order to reduce or eliminate the exposures of concern results from conditional outcome research should also be used. We therefore suggest to add a 'consequence' criterion. We argue that a consequence criterion that provides a framework for assessing or prescribing action worthy or right in social contexts is needed. A consequence criterion will also influence how strict our causal criteria need to be before leading to action and will help in separating the 'causal discussion' and the discussion on what to do about it. A consequence criterion will be a tool in handling dilemmas over values (as social solidarity, fairness, autonomy). It will have implications for the interpretation and use of the procedural criteria of causality. Establishing interconnected procedural and consequence criteria should be a task for institutions representing and being recognized by experts, civil society and the state.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Jørn Olsen
- Department of Clinical Epidemiology, Aarhus University Hospital, Olof Palmes Alle 43-45, 8200, Aarhus N, Denmark.
| | - Uffe Juul Jensen
- Department of Philosophy and History of Ideas, School of Culture and Society, Aarhus University, Building 1465, Jens Chr. Skous Vej 7, 8000, Aarhus C, Denmark
| |
Collapse
|
11
|
Dammann O. Hill's Heuristics and Explanatory Coherentism in Epidemiology. Am J Epidemiol 2018; 187:1-6. [PMID: 29121224 DOI: 10.1093/aje/kwx216] [Citation(s) in RCA: 6] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.9] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 04/06/2016] [Accepted: 04/04/2017] [Indexed: 12/28/2022] Open
Abstract
In this essay, I argue that Ted Poston's theory of explanatory coherentism is well-suited as a tool for causal explanation in the health sciences, particularly in epidemiology. Coherence has not only played a role in epidemiology for more than half a century as one of Hill's viewpoints, it can also provide background theory for the development of explanatory systems by integrating epidemiologic evidence with a diversity of other error-independent data. I propose that computational formalization of Hill's viewpoints in an explanatory coherentist framework would provide an excellent starting point for a formal epistemological (knowledge-theoretical) project designed to improve causal explanation in the health sciences. As an example, I briefly introduce Paul Thagard's ECHO system and offer my responses to possible objections to my proposal.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Olaf Dammann
- Department of Public Health and Community Medicine, Tufts University School of Medicine, Boston, Massachusetts
| |
Collapse
|
12
|
Greenland S. For and Against Methodologies: Some Perspectives on Recent Causal and Statistical Inference Debates. Eur J Epidemiol 2017; 32:3-20. [PMID: 28220361 DOI: 10.1007/s10654-017-0230-6] [Citation(s) in RCA: 42] [Impact Index Per Article: 5.3] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Accepted: 01/30/2017] [Indexed: 01/22/2023]
Abstract
I present an overview of two methods controversies that are central to analysis and inference: That surrounding causal modeling as reflected in the "causal inference" movement, and that surrounding null bias in statistical methods as applied to causal questions. Human factors have expanded what might otherwise have been narrow technical discussions into broad philosophical debates. There seem to be misconceptions about the requirements and capabilities of formal methods, especially in notions that certain assumptions or models (such as potential-outcome models) are necessary or sufficient for valid inference. I argue that, once these misconceptions are removed, most elements of the opposing views can be reconciled. The chief problem of causal inference then becomes one of how to teach sound use of formal methods (such as causal modeling, statistical inference, and sensitivity analysis), and how to apply them without generating the overconfidence and misinterpretations that have ruined so many statistical practices.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Sander Greenland
- Department of Epidemiology and Department of Statistics, University of California, Los Angeles, CA, USA.
| |
Collapse
|
13
|
Balagué F, Pellisé F. Adolescent idiopathic scoliosis and back pain. SCOLIOSIS AND SPINAL DISORDERS 2016; 11:27. [PMID: 27648474 PMCID: PMC5016859 DOI: 10.1186/s13013-016-0086-7] [Citation(s) in RCA: 49] [Impact Index Per Article: 5.4] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Download PDF] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 02/04/2016] [Accepted: 08/18/2016] [Indexed: 11/24/2022]
Abstract
This broad narrative review addresses the relationship between adolescent idiopathic scoliosis (AIS) and back pain. AIS can be responsible for low back pain, particularly major cases. However, a linear relationship between back pain and the magnitude of the deformity cannot be expected for any individual patient. A large number of juvenile patients can remain pain-free. The long-term prognosis is rather benign for many cases and thus a tailored approach to the individual patient seems mandatory. The level of evidence available does not allow stringent recommendations for any of the disorders included in this review.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Federico Balagué
- Department of Rheumatology, HFR Fribourg-Hôpital Cantonal, 1708 Fribourg, Switzerland ; University of Geneva, Geneva, Switzerland ; Department of Orthopedics, NYU, New York, USA
| | - Ferran Pellisé
- Spine Unit, Hospital Vall Hebron, 08035 Barcelona, Spain ; Spine Unit Hospital Quirón, 08023 Barcelona, Spain
| |
Collapse
|
14
|
Shrader-Frechette K, ChoGlueck C. Pesticides, Neurodevelopmental Disagreement, and Bradford Hill’s Guidelines. Account Res 2016; 24:30-42. [DOI: 10.1080/08989621.2016.1203786] [Citation(s) in RCA: 3] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.3] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 12/26/2022]
|
15
|
Listl S, Jürges H, Watt RG. Causal inference from observational data. Community Dent Oral Epidemiol 2016; 44:409-15. [DOI: 10.1111/cdoe.12231] [Citation(s) in RCA: 42] [Impact Index Per Article: 4.7] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 01/14/2016] [Accepted: 03/20/2016] [Indexed: 11/29/2022]
Affiliation(s)
- Stefan Listl
- Department of Conservative Dentistry; Translational Health Economics Group (THE Group); Heidelberg University; Heidelberg Germany
- Munich Center for the Economics of Aging; Max-Planck-Institute for Social Law and Social Policy; Munich Germany
| | - Hendrik Jürges
- Schumpeter School of Business and Economics; University of Wuppertal; Wuppertal Germany
| | - Richard G. Watt
- Department of Epidemiology and Public Health; University College London; London United Kingdom
| |
Collapse
|
16
|
Sizochenko N, Gajewicz A, Leszczynski J, Puzyn T. Causation or only correlation? Application of causal inference graphs for evaluating causality in nano-QSAR models. NANOSCALE 2016; 8:7203-8. [PMID: 26972917 DOI: 10.1039/c5nr08279j] [Citation(s) in RCA: 8] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.9] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 05/03/2023]
Abstract
In this paper, we suggest that causal inference methods could be efficiently used in Quantitative Structure-Activity Relationships (QSAR) modeling as additional validation criteria within quality evaluation of the model. Verification of the relationships between descriptors and toxicity or other activity in the QSAR model has a vital role in understanding the mechanisms of action. The well-known phrase "correlation does not imply causation" reflects insight statistically correlated with the endpoint descriptor may not cause the emergence of this endpoint. Hence, paradigmatic shifts must be undertaken when moving from traditional statistical correlation analysis to causal analysis of multivariate data. Methods of causal discovery have been applied for broader physical insight into mechanisms of action and interpretation of the developed nano-QSAR models. Previously developed nano-QSAR models for toxicity of 17 nano-sized metal oxides towards E. coli bacteria have been validated by means of the causality criteria. Using the descriptors confirmed by the causal technique, we have developed new models consistent with the straightforward causal-reasoning account. It was proven that causal inference methods are able to provide a more robust mechanistic interpretation of the developed nano-QSAR models.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Natalia Sizochenko
- Laboratory of Environmental Chemometrics, Faculty of Chemistry, University of Gdansk, Wita Stwosza 63, 80-308, Gdansk, Poland. and Interdisciplinary Center for Nanotoxicity, Department of Chemistry, Jackson State University, 1400 J. R. Lynch Street, P. O. Box 17910, Jackson, MS 39217, USA
| | - Agnieszka Gajewicz
- Laboratory of Environmental Chemometrics, Faculty of Chemistry, University of Gdansk, Wita Stwosza 63, 80-308, Gdansk, Poland.
| | - Jerzy Leszczynski
- Interdisciplinary Center for Nanotoxicity, Department of Chemistry, Jackson State University, 1400 J. R. Lynch Street, P. O. Box 17910, Jackson, MS 39217, USA
| | - Tomasz Puzyn
- Laboratory of Environmental Chemometrics, Faculty of Chemistry, University of Gdansk, Wita Stwosza 63, 80-308, Gdansk, Poland.
| |
Collapse
|
17
|
Hulme A, Finch CF. From monocausality to systems thinking: a complementary and alternative conceptual approach for better understanding the development and prevention of sports injury. Inj Epidemiol 2015; 2:31. [PMID: 26691678 PMCID: PMC4673096 DOI: 10.1186/s40621-015-0064-1] [Citation(s) in RCA: 71] [Impact Index Per Article: 7.1] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Download PDF] [Figures] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 09/07/2015] [Accepted: 12/03/2015] [Indexed: 11/10/2022] Open
Abstract
The science of sports injury control, including both its cause and prevention, has largely been informed by a biomedical and mechanistic model of health. Traditional scientific practice in sports injury research has routinely involved collapsing the broader socioecological landscape down in order to analyse individual-level determinants of injury - whether biomechanical and/or behavioural. This approach has made key gains for sports injury prevention research and should be further encouraged and allowed to evolve naturally. However, the public health, Applied Human Factors and Ergonomics, and injury epidemiological literature more broadly, has accepted the value of a socioecological paradigm for better understanding disease and injury processes, and sports injury research will fall further behind unless it does the same. A complementary and alternative conceptual approach towards injury control known as systems thinking that builds on socioecological science, both methodologically and analytically, is readily available and fast developing in other research areas. This review outlines the historical progression of causal concepts in the field of epidemiology over the course of the modern scientific era. From here, causal concepts in injury epidemiology, and models of aetiology as found in the context of sports injury research are presented. The paper finishes by proposing a new research agenda that considers the potential for a systems thinking approach to further enhance sports injury aetiological understanding. A complementary systems paradigm, however, will require that sports injury epidemiologists bring their knowledge and skillsets forwards in an attempt to use, adapt, and even refine existing systems-based approaches. Alongside the natural development of conventional scientific methodologies and analyses in sports injury research, progressing forwards to a systems paradigm is now required.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Adam Hulme
- Australian Centre for Research into Injury in Sports and its Prevention (ACRISP), Federation University Australia, SMB Campus, PO Box 663, Ballarat, Victoria 3353 Australia
| | - Caroline F Finch
- Australian Centre for Research into Injury in Sports and its Prevention (ACRISP), Federation University Australia, SMB Campus, PO Box 663, Ballarat, Victoria 3353 Australia
| |
Collapse
|
18
|
Klurfeld DM. Research gaps in evaluating the relationship of meat and health. Meat Sci 2015; 109:86-95. [PMID: 26043666 DOI: 10.1016/j.meatsci.2015.05.022] [Citation(s) in RCA: 76] [Impact Index Per Article: 7.6] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 03/05/2015] [Accepted: 05/21/2015] [Indexed: 12/18/2022]
Abstract
Humans evolved as omnivores and it has been proposed that cooking meat allowed for evolution of larger brains that has led to our success as a species. Meat is one of the most nutrient dense foods, providing high-quality protein, heme iron, zinc, and vitamins B6 and B12. Despite these advantages, epidemiologic studies have linked consumption of red or processed meat with obesity, type 2 diabetes, cardiovascular diseases, and cancers of multiple organs. Most observational studies report small, increased relative risks. However, there are many limitations of such studies including inability to accurately estimate intake, lack of prespecified hypotheses, multiple comparisons, and confounding from many factors - including body weight, fruit/vegetable intake, physical activity, smoking, and alcohol - that correlate significantly either positively or negatively with meat intake and limit the reliability of conclusions from these studies. The observational studies are heterogeneous and do not fulfill many of the points proposed by AB Hill in 1965 for inferring causality; his most important factor was strength of the association which in dietary studies is usually <1.5 but is not considered adequate in virtually all other areas of epidemiology outside nutrition. Accepting small, statistically significant risks as "real" from observational associations, the field of nutrition has a long list of failures including beta-carotene and lung cancer, low-fat diets and breast cancer or heart disease that have not been confirmed in randomized trials. Moderate intake of a variety of foods that are enjoyed by people remains the best dietary advice.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- David M Klurfeld
- USDA Agricultural Research Service, 5601 Sunnyside Avenue, Beltsville, MD 20705-5138, United States.
| |
Collapse
|
19
|
Carmichael SL. Birth defects epidemiology. Eur J Med Genet 2014; 57:355-8. [DOI: 10.1016/j.ejmg.2014.03.002] [Citation(s) in RCA: 21] [Impact Index Per Article: 1.9] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 01/17/2014] [Accepted: 03/03/2014] [Indexed: 11/28/2022]
|
20
|
Simon TW, Simons SS, Preston RJ, Boobis AR, Cohen SM, Doerrer NG, Fenner-Crisp PA, McMullin TS, McQueen CA, Rowlands JC. The use of mode of action information in risk assessment: Quantitative key events/dose-response framework for modeling the dose-response for key events. Crit Rev Toxicol 2014; 44 Suppl 3:17-43. [DOI: 10.3109/10408444.2014.931925] [Citation(s) in RCA: 51] [Impact Index Per Article: 4.6] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 12/29/2022]
|
21
|
Thomas J, O'Mara-Eves A, Brunton G. Using qualitative comparative analysis (QCA) in systematic reviews of complex interventions: a worked example. Syst Rev 2014; 3:67. [PMID: 24950727 PMCID: PMC4079172 DOI: 10.1186/2046-4053-3-67] [Citation(s) in RCA: 70] [Impact Index Per Article: 6.4] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [Track Full Text] [Download PDF] [Figures] [Journal Information] [Submit a Manuscript] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 03/17/2014] [Accepted: 05/30/2014] [Indexed: 11/10/2022] Open
Abstract
BACKGROUND Systematic reviews that address policy and practice questions in relation to complex interventions frequently need not only to assess the efficacy of a given intervention but to identify which intervention - and which intervention components - might be most effective in particular situations. Here, intervention replication is rare, and commonly used synthesis methods are less useful when the focus of analysis is the identification of those components of an intervention that are critical to its success. METHODS Having identified initial theories of change in a previous analysis, we explore the potential of qualitative comparative analysis (QCA) to assist with complex syntheses through a worked example. Developed originally in the area of political science and historical sociology, a QCA aims to identify those configurations of participant, intervention and contextual characteristics that may be associated with a given outcome. Analysing studies in these terms facilitates the identification of necessary and sufficient conditions for the outcome to be obtained. Since QCA is predicated on the assumption that multiple pathways might lead to the same outcome and does not assume a linear additive model in terms of changes to a particular condition (that is, it can cope with 'tipping points' in complex interventions), it appears not to suffer from some of the limitations of the statistical methods often used in meta-analysis. RESULTS The worked example shows how the QCA reveals that our initial theories of change were unable to distinguish between 'effective' and 'highly effective' interventions. Through the iterative QCA process, other intervention characteristics are identified that better explain the observed results. CONCLUSIONS QCA is a promising alternative (or adjunct), particularly to the standard fall-back of a 'narrative synthesis' when a quantitative synthesis is impossible, and should be considered when reviews are broad and heterogeneity is significant. There are very few examples of its use with systematic review data at present, and further methodological work is needed to establish optimal conditions for its use and to document process, practice, and reporting standards.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- James Thomas
- EPPI-Centre, Social Science Research Unit, Institute of Education, 18 Woburn Square, London WC1H 0NR, UK.
| | | | | |
Collapse
|
22
|
Moore PS, Chang Y. The conundrum of causality in tumor virology: the cases of KSHV and MCV. Semin Cancer Biol 2014; 26:4-12. [PMID: 24304907 PMCID: PMC4040341 DOI: 10.1016/j.semcancer.2013.11.001] [Citation(s) in RCA: 27] [Impact Index Per Article: 2.5] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [MESH Headings] [Grants] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 10/10/2013] [Accepted: 11/13/2013] [Indexed: 01/18/2023]
Abstract
Controversy has plagued tumor virology since the first tumor viruses were described over 100 years ago. Methods to establish cancer causation, such as Koch's postulates, work poorly or not at all for these viruses. Kaposi's sarcoma herpesvirus (KSHV/HHV8) and Merkel cell polyomavirus (MCV) were both found using nucleic acid identification methods but they represent opposite poles in the patterns for tumor virus epidemiology. KSHV is uncommon and has specific risk factors that contribute to infection and subsequent cancers. MCV and Merkel cell carcinoma (MCC), in contrast, is an example in which mutations to our normal viral flora contribute to cancer. Given the near-ubiquity of human MCV infection, establishing cancer causality relies on molecular evidence that does not fit comfortably within traditional infectious disease epidemiological models. These two viruses reveal some of the challenges and opportunities for inferring viral cancer causation in the age of molecular biology.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Patrick S Moore
- Cancer Virology Program, University of Pittsburgh Cancer Institute, 5117 Centre Avenue, Pittsburgh, PA 15213, United States.
| | - Yuan Chang
- Cancer Virology Program, University of Pittsburgh Cancer Institute, 5117 Centre Avenue, Pittsburgh, PA 15213, United States.
| |
Collapse
|
23
|
Morabia A. Hume, Mill, Hill, and the sui generis epidemiologic approach to causal inference. Am J Epidemiol 2013; 178:1526-32. [PMID: 24071010 DOI: 10.1093/aje/kwt223] [Citation(s) in RCA: 19] [Impact Index Per Article: 1.6] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Key Words] [MESH Headings] [Grants] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 12/26/2022] Open
Abstract
The epidemiologic approach to causal inference (i.e., Hill's viewpoints) consists of evaluating potential causes from the following 2, noncumulative angles: 1) established results from comparative, observational, or experimental epidemiologic studies; and 2) reviews of nonepidemiologic evidence. It does not involve statements of statistical significance. The philosophical roots of Hill's viewpoints are unknown. Superficially, they seem to descend from the ideas of Hume and Mill. Hill's viewpoints, however, use a different kind of evidence and have different purposes than do Hume's rules or Mill's system of logic. In a nutshell, Hume ignores comparative evidence central to Hill's viewpoints. Mill's logic disqualifies as invalid nonexperimental evidence, which forms the bulk of epidemiologic findings reviewed from Hill's viewpoints. The approaches by Hume and Mill cannot corroborate successful implementations of Hill's viewpoints. Besides Hume and Mill, the epidemiologic literature is clueless about a plausible, pre-1965 philosophical origin of Hill's viewpoints. Thus, Hill's viewpoints may be philosophically novel, sui generis, still waiting to be validated and justified.
Collapse
|
24
|
Generalizability and scalability of HIV 'treatment as prevention'. AIDS 2013; 27:2493-4. [PMID: 24029737 DOI: 10.1097/01.aids.0000432468.61626.d4] [Citation(s) in RCA: 0] [Impact Index Per Article: 0] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 11/26/2022]
|
25
|
Espinoza J. Uteroplacental ischemia in early- and late-onset pre-eclampsia: a role for the fetus? ULTRASOUND IN OBSTETRICS & GYNECOLOGY : THE OFFICIAL JOURNAL OF THE INTERNATIONAL SOCIETY OF ULTRASOUND IN OBSTETRICS AND GYNECOLOGY 2012; 40:373-382. [PMID: 23161443 DOI: 10.1002/uog.12280] [Citation(s) in RCA: 13] [Impact Index Per Article: 1.0] [Reference Citation Analysis] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 06/01/2023]
Affiliation(s)
- J Espinoza
- Department of Obstetrics and Gynecology, Texas Children's Hospital Pavilion for Women, Baylor College of Medicine, 6651 Main Street, Suite 1020, Houston, TX 77030, USA.
| |
Collapse
|
26
|
Sloboda Z, Glantz MD, Tarter RE. Revisiting the concepts of risk and protective factors for understanding the etiology and development of substance use and substance use disorders: implications for prevention. Subst Use Misuse 2012; 47:944-62. [PMID: 22676565 DOI: 10.3109/10826084.2012.663280] [Citation(s) in RCA: 53] [Impact Index Per Article: 4.1] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Submit a Manuscript] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 12/22/2022]
Abstract
Over the past 20 years we have accumulated a greater knowledge and understanding of the genetic, neurobiological, and behavioral factors that may be associated with young people initiating the use of drugs and other substances and to progressing from use to abuse and dependence. This knowledge suggests that individuals may be "predisposed" to substance use disorders (SUD) and that the actual engagement in these behaviors depends on their environmental experiences from micro to macro levels. This paper summarizes this knowledge base and supports a developmental framework that examines the interaction of posited genetic, psychological, and neurobiological "predispositions" to SUD and those environmental influences that exacerbate this vulnerability.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Zili Sloboda
- Research and Development Group, JBS International, Inc., 5515 Security Lane, North Bethesda, MD 20852, USA.
| | | | | |
Collapse
|
27
|
Abstract
Forensic pathologists make inferences about cause and manner of death. Those inferences have come under increasing scrutiny by the courts, by social critics of our findings, and by society at large. Much of this criticism is due to our inability to explain our inferential process. Forensic pathologists should be able to cogently explain the reasoning behind their findings, and express it in terms useful to stakeholders. This requires that we have a basic understanding of different kinds of inference and the scientific method, how they are used and their limitations. Medical diagnosis is not a simple matter of application of cookbook-style inferential laws, but involves a combination of deduction, induction, abduction, dialectic, and informal inference. There are significant differences between the way physicians make inferences compared to how they justify them. A discussion of different kinds of inference, inferential fallacies, evaluation of evidence, causation, and the scientific method is provided, with illustrations from the practice of forensic pathology.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- William R. Oliver
- Pathology and Laboratory Medicine at Brody School of Medicine at East Carolina University in Greenville, NC, Chief Medical Examiner, State of North Carolina
| |
Collapse
|
28
|
Madsen AM, Hodge SE, Ottman R. Causal models for investigating complex disease: I. A primer. Hum Hered 2011; 72:54-62. [PMID: 21912138 DOI: 10.1159/000330779] [Citation(s) in RCA: 17] [Impact Index Per Article: 1.2] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 04/02/2011] [Accepted: 07/11/2011] [Indexed: 12/23/2022] Open
Abstract
BACKGROUND/AIMS To illustrate the utility of causal models for research in genetic epidemiology and statistical genetics. Causal models are increasingly applied in risk factor epidemiology, economics, and health policy, but seldom used in statistical genetics or genetic epidemiology. Unlike the statistical models usually used in genetic epidemiology, causal models are explicitly formulated in terms of cause and effect relationships occurring at the individual level. METHODS We describe two causal models, the sufficient component cause model and the potential outcomes model, and show how key concepts in genetic epidemiology, including penetrance, phenocopies, genetic heterogeneity, etiologic heterogeneity, gene-gene interaction, and gene-environment interaction, can be framed in terms of these causal models. We also illustrate how potential outcomes models can provide insight into the potential for confounding and bias in the measurement of causal effects in genetic studies. RESULTS Our analysis illustrates how causal models can elucidate the relationships among underlying causal mechanisms and measures obtained from statistical analysis of observed data. CONCLUSION Causal models can enhance research aimed at identifying causal genes.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Ann M Madsen
- Department of Epidemiology, Mailman School of Public Health, Columbia University, New York, USA
| | | | | |
Collapse
|
29
|
Chan V, Burwash IG, Lam BK, Auyeung T, Tran A, Mesana TG, Ruel M. Clinical and Echocardiographic Impact of Functional Tricuspid Regurgitation Repair at the Time of Mitral Valve Replacement. Ann Thorac Surg 2009; 88:1209-15. [DOI: 10.1016/j.athoracsur.2009.06.034] [Citation(s) in RCA: 86] [Impact Index Per Article: 5.4] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Submit a Manuscript] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 02/08/2009] [Revised: 06/08/2009] [Accepted: 06/12/2009] [Indexed: 10/20/2022]
|
30
|
Ward AC. The role of causal criteria in causal inferences: Bradford Hill's "aspects of association". EPIDEMIOLOGIC PERSPECTIVES & INNOVATIONS : EP+I 2009; 6:2. [PMID: 19534788 PMCID: PMC2706236 DOI: 10.1186/1742-5573-6-2] [Citation(s) in RCA: 85] [Impact Index Per Article: 5.3] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Track Full Text] [Download PDF] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 08/11/2008] [Accepted: 06/17/2009] [Indexed: 11/10/2022]
Abstract
As noted by Wesley Salmon and many others, causal concepts are ubiquitous in every branch of theoretical science, in the practical disciplines and in everyday life. In the theoretical and practical sciences especially, people often base claims about causal relations on applications of statistical methods to data. However, the source and type of data place important constraints on the choice of statistical methods as well as on the warrant attributed to the causal claims based on the use of such methods. For example, much of the data used by people interested in making causal claims come from non-experimental, observational studies in which random allocations to treatment and control groups are not present. Thus, one of the most important problems in the social and health sciences concerns making justified causal inferences using non-experimental, observational data. In this paper, I examine one method of justifying such inferences that is especially widespread in epidemiology and the health sciences generally - the use of causal criteria. I argue that while the use of causal criteria is not appropriate for either deductive or inductive inferences, they do have an important role to play in inferences to the best explanation. As such, causal criteria, exemplified by what Bradford Hill referred to as "aspects of [statistical] associations", have an indispensible part to play in the goal of making justified causal claims.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Andrew C Ward
- Minnesota Population Center, University of Minnesota, Minneapolis, MN 55455, USA.
| |
Collapse
|
31
|
Knol AB, Petersen AC, van der Sluijs JP, Lebret E. Dealing with uncertainties in environmental burden of disease assessment. Environ Health 2009; 8:21. [PMID: 19400963 PMCID: PMC2684742 DOI: 10.1186/1476-069x-8-21] [Citation(s) in RCA: 36] [Impact Index Per Article: 2.3] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [MESH Headings] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 01/30/2009] [Accepted: 04/28/2009] [Indexed: 05/07/2023]
Abstract
Disability Adjusted Life Years (DALYs) combine the number of people affected by disease or mortality in a population and the duration and severity of their condition into one number. The environmental burden of disease is the number of DALYs that can be attributed to environmental factors. Environmental burden of disease estimates enable policy makers to evaluate, compare and prioritize dissimilar environmental health problems or interventions. These estimates often have various uncertainties and assumptions which are not always made explicit. Besides statistical uncertainty in input data and parameters - which is commonly addressed - a variety of other types of uncertainties may substantially influence the results of the assessment. We have reviewed how different types of uncertainties affect environmental burden of disease assessments, and we give suggestions as to how researchers could address these uncertainties. We propose the use of an uncertainty typology to identify and characterize uncertainties. Finally, we argue that uncertainties need to be identified, assessed, reported and interpreted in order for assessment results to adequately support decision making.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Anne B Knol
- National Institute for Public Health and the Environment (RIVM), Bilthoven, the Netherlands
| | - Arthur C Petersen
- Netherlands Environmental Assessment Agency (PBL), Bilthoven, the Netherlands
| | - Jeroen P van der Sluijs
- Copernicus Institute for Sustainable Development and Innovation, Utrecht University, the Netherlands
- Centre d'Economie et d'Ethique pour l'Environnement et le Développement, Université de Versailles Saint-Quentin-en-Yvelines, France
- Institute for Risk Assessment Sciences (IRAS), Utrecht University, the Netherlands
| | - Erik Lebret
- National Institute for Public Health and the Environment (RIVM), Bilthoven, the Netherlands
- Institute for Risk Assessment Sciences (IRAS), Utrecht University, the Netherlands
| |
Collapse
|
32
|
Iversen BG, Hofmann B, Aavitsland P. Questions on causality and responsibility arising from an outbreak of Pseudomonas aeruginosa infections in Norway. Emerg Themes Epidemiol 2008; 5:22. [PMID: 18947429 PMCID: PMC2585074 DOI: 10.1186/1742-7622-5-22] [Citation(s) in RCA: 3] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.2] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Track Full Text] [Download PDF] [Figures] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 04/25/2008] [Accepted: 10/23/2008] [Indexed: 11/10/2022] Open
Abstract
In 2002, Norway experienced a large outbreak of Pseudomonas aeruginosa infections in hospitals with 231 confirmed cases. This fuelled intense public and professional debates on what were the causes and who were responsible. In epidemiology, other sciences, in philosophy and in law there is a long tradition of discussing the concept of causality. We use this outbreak as a case; apply various theories of causality from different disciplines to discuss the roles and responsibilities of some of the parties involved. Mackie's concept of INUS conditions, Hill's nine viewpoints to study association for claiming causation, deterministic and probabilistic ways of reasoning, all shed light on the issues of causality in this outbreak. Moreover, applying legal theories of causation (counterfactual reasoning and the "but-for" test and the NESS test) proved especially useful, but the case also illustrated the weaknesses of the various theories of causation. We conclude that many factors contributed to causing the outbreak, but that contamination of a medical device in the production facility was the major necessary condition. The reuse of the medical device in hospitals contributed primarily to the size of the outbreak. The unintended error by its producer – and to a minor extent by the hospital practice – was mainly due to non-application of relevant knowledge and skills, and appears to constitute professional negligence. Due to criminal procedure laws and other factors outside the discourse of causality, no one was criminally charged for the outbreak which caused much suffering and shortening the life of at least 34 people.
Collapse
|
33
|
Martin W. Linking causal concepts, study design, analysis and inference in support of one epidemiology for population health. Prev Vet Med 2008; 86:270-88. [PMID: 18378341 DOI: 10.1016/j.prevetmed.2008.02.013] [Citation(s) in RCA: 10] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.6] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Track Full Text] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Indexed: 12/26/2022]
Abstract
In this paper, which is dedicated to Dr. Calvin Schwabe, I review the concepts of causation and how they impact on study design, analysis and interpretation of results. Notwithstanding the fact that no observational study can prove causation, there are a number of issues that if addressed sufficiently, can improve the validity and usefulness of our studies. These are elaborated with specific recommendations for the conduct of future observational research. Approaches that have been useful in my teaching and research experience are also described.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Wayne Martin
- Department of Population Medicine, University of Guelph, Guelph, Ontario, Canada N1G 2W1.
| |
Collapse
|
34
|
Höfler M. Getting causal considerations back on the right track. Emerg Themes Epidemiol 2006; 3:8. [PMID: 16854222 PMCID: PMC1557848 DOI: 10.1186/1742-7622-3-8] [Citation(s) in RCA: 9] [Impact Index Per Article: 0.5] [Reference Citation Analysis] [Abstract] [Track Full Text] [Download PDF] [Journal Information] [Subscribe] [Scholar Register] [Received: 05/23/2006] [Accepted: 07/19/2006] [Indexed: 11/10/2022] Open
Abstract
In their commentary on my paper Phillips and Goodman suggested that counterfactual causality and considerations on causality like those by Bradford Hill are only "guideposts on the road to common sense". I argue that if common sense is understood to mean views that the vast majority of researchers share, Hill's considerations did not lead to common sense in the past--precisely because they are so controversial. If common sense is taken to mean beliefs that are true, then Hill's considerations can only lead to common sense in the simple and well-understood causal systems they apply to. Counterfactuals, however, are largely common sense in the latter meaning.I suggest that the road of scientific endeavour should lead epidemiologic research toward sound strategies that equip researchers with skills to separate causal from non-causal associations with minimal error probabilities. This is undeniably the right direction and the one counterfactual causality leads to. Hill's considerations are merely heuristics with which epidemiologists may or may not find this direction, and they are likely to fail in complex landscapes (causal systems). In such environments, one might easily lose orientation without further aids (e.g., defendable assumptions on biases). Counterfactual causality tells us when and how to apply these heuristics.
Collapse
Affiliation(s)
- Michael Höfler
- Institute of Clinical Psychology and Psychotherapy, Dresden Technical University, Dresden, Germany
| |
Collapse
|